home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
-
- ### ###
- ### ###
- ### #### ### ### ### ####
- ### ### ##### ### ###
- ### ### ### ### ###
- ### ### ##### ### ###
- ########## ### ### ##########
- ### ###
- ### ###
-
- Underground eXperts United
-
- Presents...
-
- ####### ## ## ####### # # ## ## #### #######
- ## ## ## ## ##### ## ## ## ##
- #### ## ## #### # # ####### ## ##
- ## ## ## ## ##### ## ## ##
- ## ## ####### ####### # # ## ###### ##
-
- [ On Friendship ] [ By The GNN ]
-
-
- ____________________________________________________________________
- ____________________________________________________________________
-
-
-
- ON FRIENDSHIP
- by THE GNN/DualCrew-Shining/uXu
-
-
- Not only is this a long and complicated textfile, it is
- also written within the tradition of 'analytic'
- philosophy, which makes it pretty scientifically stiff
- (i.e., 'boring'). I do encourage the reader to give it a
- chance, though. The notion of friendship is not only an
- interesting concept to examine for-itself; it is an
- interpersonal relation that is most necessary for our
- lives. Some people, however, have not realized this fact,
- believing that friends come and go by themselves, that
- one need not actively uphold certain relations, as they
- are somewhat 'automatic' to their character. Nothing
- could be more wrong. As I have grown older, I have
- noticed that I am about to lose many good friends since
- they (and me too, certainly) are unable to understand
- what it takes to be a real friend. To save you from grief
- and despair in the future, I recommend you to study this
- text, and think twice what it means to truly be a 'real
- friend'. (First-time readers may omit section VIII and
- the footnotes, as they probably are only of interest for
- specialists in the field of Aristotelian ethics.)
-
-
- I. Introduction
-
- In our seemingly cold-comfort western culture, public demonstration of
- friendship is rather uncommon, limited to formalities such as greeting
- cards or handshakes. But to jump to the conclusion that there is no such
- thing as deep affection between people (which need not necessarily fall
- into the category of 'lovers') from this shallow observation would be too
- rash. A denial of the very existence of friendship and its impact on our
- lives is to misconstrue an important part of the good life. Some prefer to
- live in solitude - but I believe most of us do not.
- The term 'friendship' is often used and abused in various circumstances
- which makes it hard to get a grip of. Of course, the difficulties are not
- solely to be blamed on the excessive use of the notion. It is undoubtedly a
- complicated relation. It would clearly be a mistake to believe that it is
- possible for a philosopher to be able to easily organize and perfectly
- define all aspects involved in it. Aware of this, I do understand that this
- paper is to be understood as merely being a tentative attempt for all that
- it is worth.
- The definition will be broadly Aristotelian.(1) I will not however
- strive for an answer to the question whether this kind of human conduct is
- morally good or not. I will only argue for what I believe this special
- relation requires. These requirements will be non-instrumentality,
- irreplaceability, and the existence of mutual altruistic emotions. I will
- shortly deal with questions on how friendships evolve in our lives through
- practice, argue that it requires certain proper attitudes - 'psychological
- dispositions' - and finally that the relation in question cannot be said to
- be true if it is based upon deceit.
-
- II. Non-Instrumentality
-
- Friendship separates itself from certain other kinds of interpersonal
- relations by being essentially non-instrumental. It is not a relation like
- those which exists between business associates, doctor and patients,
- students and teachers, and so on. While a relation of friendship is upheld
- thanks to an interrelation between several complex parts, relations of the
- former kind are sought strictly for the sake of utility. They seize to be
- the very moment the purpose has been fulfilled, and the attitudes entailing
- such instrumental relations do not work very well with friendship. If we
- regard our beloved ones as mere instruments toward some personal goal (or
- universal even), as recommended in obscure publications like 'How to Win
- Friends and Influence People', we would soon find ourselves living
- alone.(2)
- This quickly calls for an objection: that there is in fact no such thing
- as a truly non-instrumental relation. We enter all relations, it could be
- said, only because we in the end want to gain something. In friendship,
- perhaps it is pleasure or self-fulfilment. The difference between business
- associates and friends would only be what they seek, not how they seek it.
- This simplification is not the whole truth though. Friendship is a more
- complex matter than that. Yes, we do gain things out of our friends. It
- would be utmost strange and even a failure if we did not. Friendship is, as
- Aristotle puts it, 'reciprocated goodwill'.(3) Friends do things for each
- other, and they gain both pleasure and self-fulfilment among other things
- out of it. But the main difference is that the various things we gain are
- results of the relation, not its primary goal (or 'focus', 'object'). It is
- no secret that an instrumental relation has as its goal the results
- themselves (money, grades, entertainment, etc.). All of the involved
- parties are aware of this. A non-instrumental ditto has as its goal the
- relation itself, and friends are aware of this too.(4) Out of this non-
- instrumentality follow several enjoyable results which would not follow if
- we regarded it instrumentally.
- The objection seems based upon a mix-up between what it means to use
- friendship as means to a further end, or to regard it as something that
- partially constitutes this end. If we find out that certain personal
- relations are necessary for, say, the good life, this does not
- automatically imply that we in all circumstances are bound to engage in
- such relations instrumentally. On the contrary, it could be a part of the
- good life, not a part to it.
- Say that I enter a relation with a car dealer for the purpose of buying
- a car. We talk and he amuses me with his jokes. He buys me coffee and shows
- me around in the shop. If one did not know the background information
- concerning my visit to the dealer, one might from mere observance believe
- that we were friends. But this is something we are not. When the car is
- bought, the relation between me and the dealer has vanished - perhaps until
- the day I need some other favor from him.(5) This would not have been the
- case if the dealer had been my friend. When I had bought the car, our
- relation would not have seized to be. Maybe I would have bought the car at
- a lower cost thanks to our relation, but I would not have used it for
- getting the car cheaper. I have not entered the relation, and I do not
- uphold it, in the intention of getting such things. Friendship is more
- about loving than being loved.(6) In a relation of utility, we strive to
- get more than we give; in friendship, we need necessarily not get more than
- we give. Certainly, friendship includes reciprocity. But this is of a
- special kind - radically different from the reciprocity existing in
- instrumental relations. Friends 'give' each other things (affection, trust,
- company, and so on) because they want to, not because they feel like they
- have to. Although we do not demand our friend to always give us something,
- we do expect that the other person is equally interested in being a friend.
- If we hang on to a relation even though we never gain anything in return at
- all, we are not really 'friends' - one of us is just exercising a form of
- unconditional love. But friendship does not and ought not require this form
- of love. As strict search for utility is unfitting, so is unconditional
- love. Friendship lies somewhere in between those two extreme point of
- views.(7) I will return to some questions concerning this in the part on
- 'irreplaceability' which will follow later.
-
- III. Emotions
-
- Per definition, friendship involves sentiments. It requires that we are
- fond of the other person.(8) It must also involve emotions of the
- altruistic kind, which is defined as a wish for the weal and woe of the
- other person for his own sake.(9) We do not expect to be let down by those
- we care about, because we believe them to care for us too. Friends trust
- each other. We dare to share with them.(10) In instrumental relations
- there can exist something that looks like such emotions. After all, the car
- dealer might with a convincing voice assure me that he wants to know if I
- am in good spirits. But what one sees is not always what one gets. Only
- because a benevolent act, as asking me if I feel all right, looks like it
- has sprung from an emotion it does not necessarily imply that it has.
- Even though goodwill and altruistic emotions are necessary parts, they
- are not all there is to friendship. I could be fully altruistic in my
- feelings and acts toward a complete stranger. But this does not mean that
- we are automatically friends. Altruistic emotions are directed toward
- particular persons in particular circumstances. Even though both my friend
- and the stranger could be in the same situation, it does not mean that I
- always feel the same for the stranger.
- Emotions of this kind have often been quite oversimplified. They are not
- seldom regarded as 'unreliable' as they are said to be too closely
- connected to 'moods'. Yes, altruistic emotions do have a tendency to change
- with the mood, but they do not seize to exist just because we do not
- temporarily 'feel' them in fullest bloom. Genuine feelings of altruism
- toward particular persons do not completely disappear with moods. If they
- do - they were hardly genuine in the first place.(11) If a friend in
- despair wants me to spend an evening with him it would be very strange if I
- refused only because 'I did not feel for it'. If it had been a complete
- stranger on the other hand, it would not have been equally surprising.
- Altruistic emotions are not 'passive'. They are active in the sense that
- they motivate us to act benevolent, out of a non-instrumental
- perspective.(12) Even though we cannot force ourselves to have certain
- emotions, this does not mean that we are equally unable to control the
- sometimes spontaneous actions that follow from them.(13) Partially due to
- the requirement of certain emotions, it seems clear that we cannot have too
- many friends. If we try to become a friend with anybody we encounter, we
- will probably just end up having a lot of 'fellows'. This is not to say
- that it is impossible to feel 'something' for large groups. Some might
- fancy certain people because they are members of a group - 'Swedes',
- 'liberals', 'table-tennis players'. But to claim that we can appreciate one
- and every member of such a group as equally good personal friends would be
- to exaggerate our emotional abilities. Imagined godlike creatures can do
- this, but we are not of that kind - and, as I will argue below, such
- 'arbitrary' manifestations of affection are inappropriate for friendship
- anyway.
-
- IV. Irreplaceability
-
- We have now reached the single most important criterion. That a friend is
- essentially irreplaceable. If I treat a stranger non-instrumentally in the
- mood of pure altruism, this does not mean that we are friends. Because, to
- me, the stranger could be any person. That he is who he is, is in fact of
- no interest. If you are my friend, on the other hand, I like you, and do
- things for you, because you are you. I like 'the whole' of you, not merely
- certain parts of your character (even though I might like some more than
- others); as your amusing jokes, your exquisite taste of automobiles or
- views of the world. What I like are not these features in themselves, but
- the combination of them: you. Even if some other person could serve my
- 'needs' for happiness and self-fulfilment better, or equally good as you, I
- would not swap. Not because you give me more pleasure qua being you, but
- because you are you and no one else. I fancy your essential features, not
- your incidental; you are (to me, at least) a unique person.
- But then, how far does this 'irreplacability' stretch? What if your
- character changes? What happens with our relation if you suddenly turn into
- a completely different person, perhaps due to a neural disease or the wrong
- company? Must I then hang on to the relation?
- No. The relation is a result of an empirical investigation, I have found
- out that I like your characteristics. If those features suddenly vanish,
- there is nothing left to like. You would not longer be you, but someone
- else, a stranger. It would be utmost strange, however, if a relation of
- friendship seized to be just because you went through some minor changes.
- After all, people do change as their lives pass by. Friendship is more
- elastic than less strong relations. If my favorite car dealer changed
- occupation, I would probably never have anything to do with him again.
- How much you must change for me to be allowed to break the relation
- without being accused for not have been a real friend is a complicated
- question and cannot be answered here, if at all. If I come from a family of
- a different culture and you, all of a sudden, turn into a hard-core
- xenophobic with certain unappealing pragmatic final solutions concerning my
- worldly existence, can we be friends? That would be utmost surprising. What
- if you are badly brain damaged in a car accident and fall into a deep coma
- that will last until your body dies? Can we be friends even though all your
- essential features are irreversibly gone? I do not think so. My emotions
- for you might last, but those alone are not all there is to friendship.
- The main issue is that it is very hard, if possible, to try to come up
- with a top-ten-style index over what one fancies with a special person, and
- how many of these features that must be around for the relation to
- last.(14)
- A fatal change need not only be that you actually turn into someone
- else. I might find out who you really are, discover something I missed when
- I first encountered you. Maybe you have only pretended to be my friend, but
- in reality simply need me as a tool for reaching some personal or universal
- goal. As I become aware of this, my trust in you will vanish. I realize
- that me-being-me does not matter in your eyes, only me-being-a-tool-for-
- some-other-end. This I cannot accept. A common complaint of friends when
- they break up is that they were manipulated and used, that they painfully
- discovered the truth beyond the other part's seemingly good intentions. We
- expect the other person to hold similar attitudes toward us as we do toward
- him or her. If we do not expect any of this from the other person, but
- still loved the person (unconditionally), we are not friends. Because we
- need not, and ought not, love the other person unconditionally in a state
- of friendship.
- Unconditional love resembles 'agape' - the kind of love that it is
- claimed that omnipotent, omniscient, good, yet imagined, godlike creatures
- feel for their creations. The 'problem' with this kind of appreciation is
- that the lover does not love the unique and irreplaceable person for what
- he is, but merely his incidental features, as 'being a human' or 'my
- creation'. But friends do not appreciate such incidental features of the
- other person, but the essential. Agape makes a person numerically
- replaceable; any person that bears the same simple qualities (like 'being
- human') deserves the same love.(15) In instrumental relations, the person
- is qualitatively replaceable, any person who bears the same qualities
- ('sells cheap cars') gets the same attention. Thus, unconditional love is
- as instrumental love not proper for friendship - because they both fail to
- appreciate the unique person.(16) Friends are phenomenologically
- irreplaceable. I cannot regard your twin brother as an equally good friend
- even if you share many characteristics. I appreciate you as a friend,
- because only you are your essential features.(17)
- Lastly, while we are at the subject of which kind of loving that is
- proper for friendship, I do not believe that friendship is the kind of
- relation that should be ascribed as existing between parents and children.
- Love does exist between both friends and family members. But '[l]ove is a
- feeling, but friendship is a state.'(18) And this kind of state is
- incompatible with the state that exists between parent-child, out of two
- main reasons.
- Firstly, it resembles the arbitrariness of unconditional love too much.
- The love of children and parents is not brought about due to an empirical
- investigation in the same sense as friends. I have perceived that I like
- your character; I have made a choice of being your friend (even though the
- choice is not as self-conscious as when we chose what to have for
- dinner).(19) Exactly why I have found this out is hard to put a finger on.
- Maybe it is because we share alike beliefs, values and interests - a shared
- conception of the good.(20) I have not just stumbled over you and without
- any further motivation come to the conclusion that we ought to be friends.
- Children do not choose their parents, and parents do not choose to have a
- child with those-and-those essential qualities.
- Secondly, friends regard each other as equals, no one having authority
- over the other, while parents (even though some would like to deny the
- force, especially concerning teenagers) believe they have the power and wit
- to determine the good for their children. This usually remains for the rest
- of their lives, since parents have the tendency to regard their offspring
- as - children, no matter how old they are.(21) Even if we look away from
- these details, which need not always be facts of the matter, I believe
- there is a more fundamental reason why claiming that children can have true
- friends is incorrect. We now partly turn to this.
-
- V. Practice
-
- If we follow Aristotle, friendship is not something we 'naturally' can do (
- as we, for example, naturally can digest the food we eat). Friendship
- requires training.(22) Not mere theoretical teaching, but practical real-
- life experiences. What we learn to do, we learn by doing. As we grow up,
- and participate in various relations, we learn more and more about what
- they really are and imply. Concerning friendship, what we learn is a
- complex concept (need for non-instrumentality, emotions, irreplaceability,
- among more). If we by some reason are unable to grasp and live by this
- concept, we will not be able to have friends.
- This means that children and animals are unable to have any friends.
- Please note that I do not claim that children or animals are unable to have
- any feelings for other creatures. What I only intend to propose is that
- friendship is a relation that is more advanced than the mere experience of
- feelings. Children lack the experience and knowledge needed. Children make
- and break 'friendships' with amazing rapidity; consult your local
- sociologist if your experiences of the real world must be supplemented with
- academic proof. After all, they have just entered the world, still not
- aware of all of its components and rules. No blame on them.
- Animals are unable to have relations of friendship out of similar
- epistemic reasons. The difference is that while children - due to the fact
- that they actually grow up - are able to obtain knowledge concerning the
- complexity of friendship. Animals are not. It is popular to claim that
- "dog is man's best friend" but unfortunately this is not true. A dog might
- be man's best 'companion' or 'fellow', but certainly not 'friend' within
- the Aristotelian definition. Friendship is solely a human conduct, since
- humans are the only ones who are able to understand the concept. Well, we
- invented it - what did you expect?
- Anyway, one could still deny this whole idea and for some reason claim
- that friendship can be the case even though the involved objects are unable
- to grasp the concept. But where will this generosity lead us? If we allow
- any kind of relation to be labelled friendship, the very term itself would
- quickly lose all meaning. My computer could be a friend of mine. It seldom
- demands anything of me (except for occasional defragmentations), and it is
- somewhat good company. Company which I can enjoy without feeling that I
- must give something back - almost like a friend! This sounds mighty strange
- in my ears.(23)
- Our best friends are often those we have had for a long time, as we have
- learned more about both the persons and how to master the appropriate
- concept.(24) Many relations changes as we grow older. We could very well
- have been involved in an instrumental relation from the beginning, but then
- swung over to a non-instrumental one. Perhaps I found out that I shared
- many other interests than automobiles with my car dealer, which eventually
- led to a state of friendship between me and him. The opposite works too:
- due to circumstances, a formerly real friend might turn into an object of
- utility. Perhaps we have grown, or moved, away from each other. Our
- interests and world-views have radically separated. We do not longer know
- each other as we used to.(25)
-
- VI. Deceit
-
- Can any form of deceived beliefs or corrupt attitudes be reconciled with
- the proper form of friendship? That all depends on which belief that is
- false or which attitude that is corrupt. Children and animals cannot have
- friends since they lack the appropriate knowledge. But what about those who
- fully know about the concepts of friendship, but in a state of it yet aim
- at something else - since they with the help of deception to a certain
- extent have 'forgotten' about this aim? Could such a person be said to
- truly be in a state of friendship?
- No. To state the obvious: I could believe I am someone's friend; but
- this belief alone does not mean that I am someone's friend. I might look
- and act as if I were a friend. Yet, this charade does not automatically
- make me one. The relation requires the above criteria, and if these are not
- fulfilled, well, when we do not have a relation of friendship. We might
- have pseudo-friendship, but that is something else.(26)
- Say that I realize that I will be able to come across a car cheaper if I
- work on becoming a friend with the dealer. I also realize that acting as a
- friend will not work if I do not believe that I really am one, as
- professional actors claim that they must truly believe that they are the
- character they play on stage to succeed. Still, they are not the character
- they play - and neither am I a friend only because I believe so. The actor
- is not really angry, happy, good, evil, while playing, but he has forced
- himself into believing so. Likewise, I do not really care for the car
- dealer, he as a unique person is not really something I value; I only make
- believe, for the sake of buying a car.
- Still, this is way too vague. What exactly is missing in pseudo-
- friendship? Well, I would not have fled to vagueness if I did not have a
- hard time putting the finger on the problem. What is for certain is that
- friendship is built upon a special set of attitudes and dispositions.
- Deception on the other hand is built upon another set, which can hardly be
- logically compatible with those required for friendship. Simply feeling
- like a friend cannot be all there is to friendship.
- But then, what would happen if it turned out that we all are deceived?
- Maybe there is no such thing as friendship in the terms described? Maybe
- all our attitudes, actions and emotions can be reduced to our sexual
- drive?(27) Or maybe we (or more precisely, me) are nothing more than brains
- in a vat, dreaming fully determined experiences. If that were so, what we
- believed to be friendship would not be so. We would not 'really' care for
- our friends, just for our personal reproduction, or, the other person in
- our dreams would not be a friend, since 'he' would be unable to have any
- kind of proper attitudes toward us. But speculations of this kind neither
- add nor reduce anything of interest from the present context. Those kinds
- of deception are totally beyond our control. There is nothing we can do,
- since we cannot have any knowledge about them. They would be incorporated
- in ourselves to the extent that they are impossible to notice. We must
- assume that the world is constituted in certain ways, otherwise we cannot
- discuss this subject at all. If these assumptions one day turn out to be
- untrue, we will have to reconsider. But that day has yet not come.
- What is of interest here is thus only the kind of deception that we
- knowingly and intentionally enters, that is, self-deception. We could
- engage in such deception in relation to friendship for a number of reasons.
- Perhaps for the sake of making money, getting to buy a car cheaper or
- preserving the world from its oncoming doom. But even though such deception
- is logically incompatible with friendship, it need not be a psychological
- problem. Our heads do not explode only because we hold incompatible
- beliefs.
- Contrary to brains-in-the-vat variants of deception, however, self-
- deception is more within our control. We create it ourselves - and what we
- create, we can pull down. This is of course not to say that it might not be
- all that easy though. But it is hardly impossible, as we are not biological
- robots that can be programmed to do anything, but simply flexible human
- beings. To claim that it is possible for us to completely alienate
- ourselves from ourselves to the extent that we never in any way notice it
- is to ascribe us capacities we do not possess. Someone suffering from deep
- insanity could of course believe anything - but such extreme cases are
- seldom due to the kind of self-deception most people practice now and then.
- As I mentioned earlier, a relation might begin on the basis of
- instrumentality, and later become one of non-instrumentality. Can
- friendship equally begin on the basis of self-deception, and then 'swing
- over' to become a genuine, non-deceived, relation? Of course it can - but
- any switch will not do. The person must first come to understand that he is
- practising self-deception. Otherwise no fundamental change will ever occur.
- This is not necessary between the switch between instrumentality and non-
- instrumentality. Because there is nothing 'hidden' in the closet of those
- relations.
-
- This concludes the main subject of this paper. In the last part I will make
- some final unfounded remarks on the notion of friendship and morality, yet
- not try to answer any question on rightness or goodness.
-
- VII. Aristotelian Friendship and Rivalling Moral Systems
-
- Ought we aim for genuine, non-deceived forms of friendship? Not obviously.
- Perhaps the world will become a much better place if more people tactically
- aimed for instrumental relations with the help of deceit. But many
- philosophers have argued that genuine friendship is one important part of a
- world that goes around in an acceptable manner. Aristotle claimed that no
- one would choose to live without friends, as it is 'most necessary for our
- lives'.(28) If this is true or an exaggeration is another discussion. But
- it seems somewhat clear that personal relations do play an important role.
- We see ourselves through others; thus, relations gives shape and meaning to
- our lives.
- But do we really have this kind of relation to those we refer to as
- 'friends' Or is the Aristotelian definition merely an ideal image that does
- not really exist, proposed by philosophical hermits who have never
- experienced how the world actually works? Even if that is so, which I
- hardly believe, the blame need not be put on the concept anyway. Perhaps
- the world has increasingly been made to make it superfluous. If so, there
- might be something wrong with the world, not with this kind of
- friendship.(29)
- It need not only be the world as we know it that makes friendship a
- practical problem however. Some moral philosophers do not hesitate to
- criticize certain ethical theories on the basis that they are unable to
- incorporate and explain the notion of friendship in a satisfying manner,
- leaving us only with the possibility of having pseudo-friends if we want to
- be fully moral. Due to this, these theories are said to malfunction, being
- only theoretical constructions which either are hard to follow as a
- personal moral theory, or, if followed, a menace to the well-being of the
- human race.
- Not all that unexpected, the defenders equally without hesitation claim
- the opposite. In a traditional philosophical manner the debate seemingly
- goes nowhere. But this is maybe not due to mutually convincing arguments,
- but because the opponents are viewing not only friendship but the whole
- concept of morality from different viewpoints.
- In between the battle between - taking the standpoints to their most
- extreme outlooks - moral theories which rest on unfounded opinions
- supported by emotional outbursts (even though some of its defenders seldom
- hesitate to claim that the to be friends.
- Chlly endorsed by 'God'), and
- theories which more resembles mathematics than moral philosophy with the
- result of being completely useless (even though the defenders seldom
- hesitate to argue that they mainly aim for the abstract notions of 'truth'
- and 'clarity') we might find a third alternative: versions of Aristotelian
- virtue ethics, despite its age still not sunk into oblivion, but then, not
- fully developed either. And even if we discover that Aristotle really had
- no acceptable moral system to offer, a closer examination of this different
- kind of ethics might perhaps help us come closer to a understanding of
- where and why the debate in question went wrong.
-
- --- (1) As put forward in the Nichomachean Ethics, book viii and ix
- (translated by Terence Irwin, Indiana: Hacket Publishing Company, 1985).
- For this paper I have also used Lawrence Blum's Friendship, Altruism and
- Morality (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul Limited, 1980), Laurence Thomas'
- article "Friendship" (Synthese, 72, 1987, pp. 217-236), but mainly Neera
- Badhwar Kapur's "Friends as Ends in Themselves" (Philosophy and
- Phenomenological Research, 48, 1987, pp. 1-23). A few less philosophical,
- but more sociological and anthropological, aspects have been found in
- Robert Brain's Friends and Lovers (London: Macgibbon Limited, 1976) and
- Rosemary Blieszner and Rebecca Adams' Adult Friendship (London: Sage
- Publications Inc., 1992).
- (2) This is not a problem which should be mixed up with those like 'the
- paradox of hedonism' or similar. It is not merely the case that we fail
- with our friendship because we view it from an instrumental angle. That
- would be to put the cart before the horse. The problem is more fundamental;
- if we view the relation from this angle, we actually have no friendship at
- all.
- (3) NE, 1155b30.
- (4) Of course, friends do not really have 'the relation' as the goal,
- but the friend himself. It is not some abstract idea of 'friendly relation'
- that is in focus, but the other person.
- (5) Aristotle do not say that it is something immediately wrong with
- relations for utility. They are useful - and we need such relations
- sometimes - but that is all. True friendships are more than useful. To
- knowingly enter a relation and fool the other person into believing that it
- is friendship, while it is not, is not a 'bad friendship', because
- friendship cannot by definition be so - it is simply some other kind of
- relation.
- (6) NE, 1159a30.
- (7) C.f. Aristotle's 'doctrine of the mean', NE book vi.
- (8) NE, 1126b20.
- (9) NE,1156a20-1158b5; Blum pp. 43-44. It should be kept in mind that
- it is not true by definition that 'altruistic acts' automatically imply
- 'self-sacrifice' or 'self-neglect'.
- (10) Laurence, 224.
- (11) Blum, p. 18, 30.
- (12) Blum, p. 13.
- (13) C.f. Aristotle 1111b15 and 1121a.
- (14) Mainly because persons are not built upon a variety of individual
- features which can be separated from each other. Persons are more of a
- bundle of features, and a few of these cannot be 'separated' from the rest,
- as they all hang together. Some features are more shallow than others -
- your way of eating or walking for example. But certainly not the most
- interesting and deep ones, as your conception of the good, those which
- really constitutes your personality. In a relation of utility with a car
- dealer it is easier to point out which feature one likes - the ability of
- selling cars, nothing more.
- (15) Aristotle points out that the most complete friendships are those
- between the most virtuous. This could mean some kind of 'god'. This,
- however, does not run counter with the arguments put forward here, as 'the
- gods' in the ancient Greece more resembled real people than the 'God' in
- Christian tradition, which is too perfect for comfort.
- (16) Kapur, pp. 5-8.
- (17) But what happens if you copy yourself in some science fiction
- device; would I regard both of you as equally good friends? I guess I would
- do. But not for long. The two of you would not be qualitatively the same _
- forever.
- (18) NE 1158a30.
- (19) Laurence, 218.
- (20) NE 1167a25, Laurence 220. Friends cannot be too alike though. The
- best friendships are those in which the involved people differ in some
- respects from each other. I would not be able to have a copy of myself as
- my best friend, as I, firstly, cannot stand people who believes they always
- know best, and secondly, would neither be able to give nor receive any new
- perspectives on my life to and from myself.
- (21) Laurence, 221-223.
- (22) Friendship is a Aristotelian virtue and all such virtues requires
- practice. See NE, book ii.
- (23) And it does not work very well with Aristotle either. 'Love for a
- soulless thing is not called friendship, since there is no mutual loving,
- and you do not wish good to it. (...) To a friend, however, it is said, you
- must wish goods for his own sake.' (NE, 1155b30.) 'Soul' need not be
- interpreted into meaning a cartesian transcendent substance, but 'those
- which posses the ability of loving' - i.e. humans.
- (24) Following from this, it is better to have few friends than many.
- Not only because we should avoid 'god-like' manifestations of arbitrary
- love, but also because good friendships cannot properly develop if we are
- unable to take the time needed for actually developing them. For the sake
- of our friends, we should take care of them and do things for them, and let
- them do things for us; but this we cannot do if they are too many. We would
- rush from friend to friend, eventually ending up with a bunch of shallow
- friendships (or none at all), (NE, 1171a10).
- (25) 'Living together is essential for the best friendship' (NE,
- 1171a30). What Aristotle meant was not 'the same house', but shared
- activities. Without the presence of such activities, friendships will
- decline. Lack of activities might be due an excess in the number of friends
- or simply because the persons are due to distance unable to spend time with
- each other. (Mere physical distance alone is not a problem nowadays,
- however, as we can use modern means of communication for those purposes.)
- (26) I have throughout this paper mainly talked about how we regard our
- friends. Is this all there is to friendship, the mere need for the proper
- set of psychological dispositions, attitudes? Maybe not. But in this
- context, complex metaphysical speculations seems superfluous, as this paper
- does not deal with the morality of friendship or its ontological status.
- (27) A popular way to come up with theories of 'natural deception' is
- by misconstruing Darwin's theories of evolution. By observing the way
- nature and mankind has evolved, some people conclude that it is
- 'scientifically proven' that we 'by nature' are only interested in the weal
- and woe of ourselves. Friendship would then be completely impossible, as it
- has been defined here. A short glance reveals though that the theories of
- evolutionary egoism in question are not 'scientific' in the usual sense, as
- they extrapolate beyond what is acceptable. They thus deserve no attention,
- unless they add something of importance to the question on how we ought to
- be. But since their conclusions are based upon how we are, and these
- conclusions are highly dubious, their prescriptions for ought becomes
- nothing more than uninteresting speculations extracted from nothing.
- (28) NE, 1155a-1155a5.
- (29) Because the Aristotelian requirements are neither radical nor
- controversial. They are not 'romantic', demanding the impossible.
- Furthermore, they are not even tied to any particular culture. A closer
- look reveals that people all over the world regards friendship as built
- upon these requirements. Certainly, people of different cultures do
- different things to demonstrate their affection - some send greeting
- cards, others cut their veins and mix blood, certain tribes in Africa throw
- excrement at their beloved ones. Striking differences indeed. But only on
- the surface. Deeper down it is virtually the same concept for everybody.
- ---
-
- ---------------------------------------------------------------------------
- uXu #417 Underground eXperts United 1998 uXu #417
- Call UNPHAMILIAR TERRITORY -> telnet upt.org
- ---------------------------------------------------------------------------
-