home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
-
- Computer underground Digest Tue Jun 20, 1995 Volume 7 : Issue 51
- ISSN 1004-042X
-
- Editors: Jim Thomas and Gordon Meyer (TK0JUT2@MVS.CSO.NIU.EDU
- Archivist: Brendan Kehoe
- Shadow Master: Stanton McCandlish
- Field Agent Extraordinaire: David Smith
- Shadow-Archivists: Dan Carosone / Paul Southworth
- Ralph Sims / Jyrki Kuoppala
- Ian Dickinson
- Triviata: How many Spams have C&S Done since April '94?
-
- CONTENTS, #7.51 (Tue, Jun 20, 1995)
-
- File 1--Against Intellectual Property
- File 2--Cu Digest Header Info (unchanged since 19 Apr, 1995)
-
- CuD ADMINISTRATIVE, EDITORIAL, AND SUBSCRIPTION INFORMATION APPEARS IN
- THE CONCLUDING FILE AT THE END OF EACH ISSUE.
-
- ---------------------------------------------------------------------
-
- From: Brian Martin <b.martin@uow.edu.au>
- Date: Tue, 30 May 1995 18.2.43 CDT
- Subject: File 1--Against Intellectual Property
-
- AGAINST INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
-
- Brian Martin
- Department of Science and Technology Studies
- University of Wollongong, NSW 2522, Australia
- email: b.martin@uow.edu.au
-
- To appear in Philosophy and Social Action, Vol. 21, No. 3, July-September
- 1995
-
-
-
- There is a strong case for opposing intellectual property. There are a number
- of negative consequences of the ownership of information, such as retarding
- of innovation and exploitation of poor countries. Most of the usual arguments
- for intellectual property do not hold up under scrutiny. In particular, the
- metaphor of the marketplace of ideas provides no justification for ownership
- of ideas. The alternative to intellectual property is that intellectual
- products not be owned, as in the case of everyday language. Strategies
- against intellectual property include civil disobedience, promotion of
- non-owned information, and fostering of a more cooperative society.
-
-
- In 1980, a book entitled Documents on Australian Defence and Foreign Policy
- 1968-1975 was published by George Munster and Richard Walsh. It reproduced
- many secret government memos, briefings and other documents concerning
- Australian involvement in the Vietnam war, events leading up to the
- Indonesian invasion of East Timor, and other issues. Exposure of this
- material deeply embarrassed the Australian government. In an unprecedented
- move, the government issued an interim injunction, citing both the Crimes Act
- and the Copyright Act. The books, just put on sale, were impounded. Print
- runs of two major newspapers with extracts from the book were also seized.
- The Australian High Court ruled that the Crimes Act did not apply, but that
- the material was protected by copyright held by the government. Later,
- Munster and Walsh produced a book using summaries and short quotes in order
- to present the information (Munster 1982).
-
- This example is one of many that shows how copyright is used to protect the
- interests of the powerful in the face of challengers, at the expense of free
- speech. Yet copyright is standardly justified on the grounds that it promotes
- creation and dissemination of ideas.
-
- Copyright is one of four main types of intellectual property or, in other
- words, ownership of information. The others are patents, trademarks and trade
- secrets. Copyright covers the expression of ideas such as in writing, music
- and pictures. Patents cover inventions, such as designs for objects or
- industrial processes. Trademarks are symbols associated with a good, service
- or company. Trade secrets cover confidential business information.
-
- The type of property that is familiar to most people is physical objects.
- People own clothes, cars, houses and land. When people own ideas, this is
- called intellectual property. But there has always been a big problem with
- owning ideas -- exclusive use or control of ideas doesn't make nearly as much
- sense as it does applied to physical objects.
-
- Many physical objects can only be used by one person at a time. If one person
- wears a pair of shoes, no one else can wear them at the same time. (The
- person who wears them often also owns them, but not always.) This is not true
- of intellectual property. Ideas can be copied over and over, but the person
- who had the original copy still has full use of it. Suppose you write a poem.
- Even if a million other people have copies and read the poem, you can still
- read the poem yourself. In other words, more than one person can use an idea
- -- a poem, a mathematical formula, a tune -- without reducing other people's
- use of the idea. Shoes and poems are fundamentally different in this respect.
-
- Technological developments have made it cheaper and easier to make copies of
- information. Printing was a great advance: it eliminated the need for hand
- copying of documents. Photocopying and computers have made it even easier to
- make copies of written documents. Photography and sound recordings have done
- the same for visual and sound material. The ability to protect intellectual
- property is being undermined by technology. Yet there is a strong push to
- expand the scope of ownership of information.
-
- This article outlines the case against intellectual property. I begin by
- mentioning some of the problems arising from ownership of information. Then I
- turn to weaknesses in the standard justifications for intellectual property.
- Next is an overview of problems with the so-called "marketplace of ideas,"
- which has important links with intellectual property. Finally, I outline some
- alternatives to intellectual property and some possible strategies for moving
- towards these alternatives.
-
- SOME PROBLEMS WITH INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
-
- Governments generate large quantities of information. They produce statistics
- on population, figures on economic production and health, texts of laws and
- regulations, and vast numbers of reports. The generation of this information
- is paid for through taxation and, therefore, it might seem that it should be
- available to any member of the public. But in some countries, some of this
- information is turned over to corporations that then sell it to whoever can
- pay. Publicly funded information is "privatised" and thus is not freely
- available (Nelkin 1984).
-
- When government-produced information is retained by the governments, things
- may not be much better. As in the case of Documents on Australian Defence and
- Foreign Policy illustrates, copyright is one technique used to keep
- information away from the public.
-
- The idea behind patents is that the fundamentals of an invention are made
- public while the inventor for a limited time has the exclusive right to make,
- use or sell the invention. But there are quite a few cases in which patents
- have been used to suppress innovation (Dunford 1987). Companies may take out
- a patent, or buy someone else's patent, in order to inhibit others from
- applying the ideas. For example, from its beginning in 1875, the US company
- AT&T collected patents in order to ensure its monopoly on telephones. It
- slowed down the introduction of radio for some 20 years. In a similar
- fashion, General Electric used control of patents to retard the introduction
- of fluorescent lights, which were a threat to its market of incandescent
- lights. Trade secrets are another way to suppress technological development.
- Trade secrets are protected by law but, unlike patents, do not have to be
- published openly.
-
- One of the newest areas to be classified as intellectual property is
- biological information. US courts have ruled that genetic sequences can be
- patented, even when the sequences are found "in nature," so long as some
- artificial means are involved in isolating them. This has led companies to
- race to take out patents on numerous genetic codes. In some cases, patents
- have been granted covering all transgenic forms of an entire species, such as
- soybeans or cotton (Mestel 1994). One consequence is a severe inhibition on
- research by non-patent holders. Another consequence is that transnational
- corporations are patenting genetic materials found in Third World plants and
- animals, so that some Third World peoples actually have to pay to use seeds
- and other genetic materials that have been freely available to them for
- centuries (Shiva and Holla-Bhar 1993).
-
- More generally, intellectual property is one more way for rich countries to
- extract wealth from poor countries. Given the enormous exploitation of poor
- peoples built into the world trade system, it would only seem fair for ideas
- produced in rich countries to be provided at no cost to poor countries. Yet
- in the GATT negotiations, representatives of rich countries, especially the
- US, have insisted on strengthening intellectual property rights. Surely there
- is no better indication that intellectual property is primarily of value to
- those who are already powerful and wealthy (Drahos 1995; Patel 1989).
-
- The potential financial returns from intellectual property are said to
- provide an incentive for individuals to create. In practice, though, most
- creators do not actually gain much benefit from intellectual property.
- Independent inventors are frequently ignored or exploited (Lancaster 1992).
- When employees of corporations and governments have an idea worth protecting,
- it is usually copyrighted or patented by the organisation, not the employee.
- Since intellectual property can be sold, it is usually the rich and powerful
- who benefit. The rich and powerful, it should be noted, seldom contribute
- much intellectual labour to the creation of new ideas.
-
- These problems -- privatisation of government information, suppression of
- patents, ownership of genetic information and information not owned by the
- true creator -- are symptoms of a deeper problem with the whole idea of
- intellectual property. Unlike goods, there are no physical obstacles to
- providing an abundance of ideas. (Indeed, the bigger problem may be an
- oversupply of ideas.) Intellectual property is an attempt to create an
- artificial scarcity in order to give rewards to a few at the expense of the
- many. Intellectual property aggravates inequality. It fosters competitiveness
- over information and ideas, whereas cooperation makes much more sense.
-
- CRITIQUE OF STANDARD JUSTIFICATIONS
-
- Edwin C. Hettinger (1989) has provided an insightful critique of the main
- arguments used to justify intellectual property, so it is worthwhile
- summarising his analysis. (See also Ricketson 1992). Hettinger begins by
- noting the obvious argument against intellectual property, namely that
- sharing intellectual objects still allows the original possessor to use them.
- Therefore, the burden of proof should lie on those who argue for intellectual
- property.
-
- The first argument for intellectual property is that people are entitled to
- the results of their labour. Hettinger's response is that not all the value
- of intellectual products is due to labour. Nor is the value of intellectual
- products due to the work of a single labourer, or any small group.
- Intellectual products are social products.
-
- Suppose you have written an essay or made an invention. Your intellectual
- work does not exist in a social vacuum. It would not have been possible
- without lots of earlier work -- both intellectual and nonintellectual -- by
- many other people. This includes your teachers and parents. It includes the
- earlier authors and inventors who have provided the foundation for your
- contribution. It also includes the many people who have discussed and used
- ideas and techniques, at both theoretical and practical levels, and provided
- a cultural foundation for your contribution. It includes the people who have
- built printing presses, laid telephone cables, built roads and buildings and
- in many other ways have contributed to the "construction" of society. Many
- other people could be mentioned. The point is that any piece of intellectual
- work is always built on and inconceivable without the prior work of numerous
- people.
-
- Hettinger points out that the earlier contributors to the development of
- ideas are not present. Today's contributor therefore cannot validly claim
- full credit.
-
- Is the market value of a piece of an intellectual product a reasonable
- indicator of a person's contribution? Certainly not. As noted by Hettinger
- and as will be discussed in the next section, markets only work once property
- rights have been established, so it is circular to argue that the market can
- be used to measure intellectual contributions. Hettinger summarises this
- point in this fashion: "The notion that a laborer is naturally entitled as a
- matter of right to receive the market value of her product is a myth. To what
- extent individual laborers should be allowed to receive the market value of
- their products is a question of social policy." (p. 39).
-
- A related argument is that people have a right to possess and personally use
- what they develop. Hettinger's response is that this doesn't show that they
- deserve market values, nor that they should have a right to prevent others
- from using the invention.
-
- A second major argument for intellectual property is that people *deserve*
- property rights because of their labour. This brings up the general issue of
- what people deserve, a topic that has been analysed by philosophers. Their
- usual conclusions go against what many people think is "common sense."
- Hettinger says that a fitting reward for labour should be proportionate to
- the person's effort, the risk taken and moral considerations. This sounds all
- right -- but it is not proportionate to the value of the results of the
- labour, whether assessed through markets or by other criteria. This is
- because the value of intellectual work is affected by things not controlled
- by the worker, including luck and natural talent. Hettinger says "A person
- who is born with extraordinary natural talents, or who is extremely lucky,
- *deserves* nothing on the basis of these characteristics" (p. 42).
-
- A musical genius like Mozart may make enormous contributions to society. But
- being born with enormous musical talents does not provide a justification for
- owning rights to musical compositions or performances. Likewise, the labour
- of developing a toy like Teenage Mutant Ninja Turtles that becomes incredibly
- popular does not provide a justification for owning rights to all possible
- uses of turtle symbols.
-
- What about a situation where one person works hard at a task and a second
- person with equal talent works less hard? Doesn't the first worker deserve
- more reward? Perhaps so, but it is not obvious that property rights provide a
- suitable mechanism for allocating rewards, especially since the market
- disproportionately rewards the person who successfully claims property rights
- for a discovery.
-
- A third argument for intellectual property is that private property is a
- means for promoting privacy and a means for personal autonomy. Hettinger
- responds that privacy is protected by not revealing information, not by
- owning it. Trade secrets cannot be defended on the grounds of privacy,
- because corporations are not individuals. As for personal autonomy,
- copyrights and patents aren't required for this.
-
- A fourth argument is that rights in intellectual property are needed to
- promote the creation of more ideas. Hettinger thinks that this is the only
- argument for intellectual property that has a possibility of standing up to
- critique. He is still somewhat sceptical, though. He notes that the whole
- argument is built on a contradiction, namely that in order to promote the
- development of ideas, it is necessary to reduce the freedom with which people
- can use them.
-
- This argument for intellectual property cannot be resolved without further
- investigation. Hettinger says that there needs to be an investigation of how
- long patents and copyrights should be granted, to determine an optimum period
- for promoting intellectual work. It should be noted that although the scale
- and pace of intellectual work has increased over the past few centuries, the
- length of protection of intellectual property has not been reduced, as might
- be expected, but greatly increased. The United States got along fine without
- copyright for much of the 1800s. Where once copyrights were only for a period
- of a few years, they now may be for the life of the author plus 50 years. In
- many countries, chemicals and pharmaceuticals were not patentable until
- recently (Patel 1989). This suggests that even if intellectual property can
- be justified on the basis of fostering new ideas, this is not the driving
- force behind the present system of copyrights and patents.
-
- THE MARKETPLACE OF IDEAS
-
- The idea of intellectual property has a number of connections with the
- concept of the marketplace of ideas, a metaphor that is widely used in
- discussions of free speech. To delve a bit more deeply into the claim that
- intellectual property promotes development of new ideas, it is therefore
- helpful to scrutinise the concept of the marketplace of ideas.
-
- The image conveyed by the marketplace of ideas is that ideas compete for
- acceptance in a market. As long as the competition is fair -- which means
- that all ideas and contributors are permitted access to the marketplace --
- then good ideas will win out over bad ones. Why? Because people will
- recognise the truth and value of good ideas. On the other hand, if the market
- is constrained, for example by some groups being excluded, then certain ideas
- cannot be tested and examined and successful ideas may not be the best ideas.
-
- Logically, there is no reason why a marketplace of ideas has to be a
- marketplace of *owned* ideas: intellectual property cannot be strictly
- justified by the marketplace of ideas. But because the marketplace metaphor
- is an economic one, there is a strong tendency to link intellectual property
- with the marketplace of ideas. As will be discussed later, there is indeed a
- link between these two concepts, but not in the way their defenders usually
- imagine.
-
- There are plenty of practical examples of the failure of the marketplace of
- ideas. Groups that are stigmatised or that lack power seldom have their
- viewpoints presented. This includes ethnic minorities, prisoners, the
- unemployed, manual workers and radical critics of the status quo, among many
- others (McGaffey 1972). Even when such groups organise themselves to promote
- their ideas, their views are often ignored while the media focus on their
- protests, as in the case of peace movement rallies and marches (Gwyn 1966).
-
- Demonstrably, good ideas do not always win out in the marketplace of ideas.
- To take one example, it can hardly be argued that the point of view of
- workers is inherently less worthy than that of employers. Yet there is an
- enormous imbalance in the presentation of their respective viewpoints in the
- media. One result is that quite a few ideas that happen to serve the
- interests of employers at the expense of workers -- such as that the reason
- people don't have jobs is because they aren't trying hard enough to find them
- -- are widely accepted although they are rejected by virtually all informed
- analysts.
-
- There is a simple and fundamental reason for the failure of the marketplace
- of ideas: inequality, especially economic inequality (Baker 1989; Hanson
- 1981). Perhaps in a group of people sitting in a room discussing an issue,
- there is some prospect of a measured assessment of different ideas. But if
- these same people are isolated in front of their television sets, and one of
- them owns the television station, it is obvious that there is little basis
- for testing of ideas. The reality is that powerful and rich groups can
- promote their ideas with little chance of rebuttal from those with different
- perspectives. Large corporations pay for advertisements and other forms of
- marketing. Governments shape media agendas as well as directly regulating the
- media. The mass media themselves are powerful enterprises -- whether owned by
- government or industry -- that promote their own interests as well as those
- of their advertisers (Bagdikian 1993).
-
- In circumstances where participants are approximate equals, such as
- intellectual discourse among peers in an academic discipline, then the
- metaphor of competition of ideas has some value. But ownership of media or
- ideas is hardly a prerequisite for such discourses. It is the equality of
- power that is essential. When, to take one of many possible examples,
- employees in corporations lack the freedom to speak openly without penalty
- (Ewing 1977), they cannot be equal participants in discourse.
-
- Some ideas are good -- in the sense of being valuable to society -- but are
- unwelcome. Some are unwelcome to powerful groups, such as that governments
- and corporations commit massive crimes (Ross 1995) or that there is a massive
- trade in technologies of torture and repression that needs to be stopped
- (Wright 1991). Others are challenging to much of the population, such as that
- imprisonment does not reduce the crime rate or that financial rewards for
- good work on the job or grades for good schoolwork are counterproductive
- (Kohn 1993). (Needless to say, individuals might disagree with the examples
- used here. The case does not rest on the examples themselves, but on the
- existence of some important cases where unwelcome but socially valuable ideas
- are marginalised.) The marketplace of ideas simply does not work to treat
- such unwelcome ideas with the seriousness they deserve. The mass media try to
- gain audiences by pleasing them, not by confronting them with challenging
- ideas (Entman 1989).
-
- The marketplace of ideas is often used to justify free speech. The argument
- is that free speech is necessary in order for the marketplace of ideas to
- operate: if some types of speech are curtailed, certain ideas will not be
- available on the marketplace and thus the best ideas will not succeed. This
- sounds plausible. But it is possible to reject the marketplace of ideas while
- still defending free speech on the grounds that it is essential to human
- liberty (Baker 1989). Conversely, defending free speech does not mean
- supporting the mass media (Lichtenberg 1987).
-
- If the marketplace of ideas doesn't work, what is the solution? The usual
- view is that governments should intervene to ensure that all groups have fair
- access to the media (McGaffey 1972). But this approach, based on promoting
- equality of opportunity, ignores the fundamental problem of economic
- inequality. Even if minority groups have some limited chance to present their
- views in the mass media, this can hardly compensate for the massive power of
- governments and corporations to promote their views. In addition, it retains
- the role of the mass media as the central mechanism for disseminating ideas.
- So-called reform proposals either retain the status quo or introduce
- government censorship (Ingber 1984).
-
- Underlying the market model is the idea of self-regulation: the "free market"
- is supposed to operate without outside intervention and, indeed, to operate
- best when outside intervention is minimised. In practice, even markets in
- goods do not operate autonomously: the state is intimately involved in even
- the freest of markets (Moran and Wright 1991). In the case of the marketplace
- of ideas, the state is involved both in shaping the market and in making it
- possible, for example by promoting and regulating the mass media. The world's
- most powerful state, the US, has been the driving force behind the
- establishment of a highly protectionist system of intellectual property,
- using power politics at GATT, the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade
- (Drahos 1995).
-
- Courts may use the rhetoric of the marketplace of ideas but actually
- interpret the law to support the status quo (Ingber 1984). For example,
- speech is treated as free until it might actually have some consequences.
- Then it is curtailed when it allegedly presents a "clear and present danger,"
- such as when peace activists expose information supposedly threatening to
- "national security" (Gleditsch 1987). But speech without action is pointless.
- True liberty requires freedom to promote one's views in practice (Baker
- 1989). Powerful groups have the ability to do this. Courts only intervene
- when others try to do the same.
-
- As in the case of trade generally, a property-based "free market" serves the
- interests of powerful producers. In the case of ideas, this includes not only
- governments and corporations but also intellectuals and professionals linked
- with universities, entertainment, journalism and the arts. Against such an
- array of intellectual opinion, it is very difficult for other groups, such as
- manual workers, to compete (Ginsberg 1986). The marketplace of ideas is a
- biased and artificial market that mostly serves to fine-tune relations
- between elites and provide them with legitimacy (Ingber 1984).
-
- The implication of this analysis is that intellectual property cannot be
- justified on the basis of the marketplace of ideas. The utilitarian argument
- for intellectual property is that ownership is necessary to stimulate
- production of new ideas, because of the financial incentive. This financial
- incentive is supposed to come from the market, whose justification is the
- marketplace of ideas. If, as critics argue, the marketplace of ideas is
- flawed by the presence of economic inequality and, more fundamentally, is an
- artificial creation that serves powerful producers of ideas and legitimates
- the role of elites, then the case for intellectual property is unfounded.
- Intellectual property can only serve to aggravate the inequality on which it
- is built.
-
-
- THE ALTERNATIVE
-
- The alternative to intellectual property is straightforward: intellectual
- products should not be owned. That means not owned by individuals,
- corporations, governments, or the community as common property. It means that
- ideas are available to be used by anyone who wants to.
-
- One example of how this might operate is language, including the words,
- sounds and meaning systems with which we communicate every day. Spoken
- language is free for everyone to use. To allow any group to own language
- raises the spectre of George Orwell's 1984. (Actually, corporations do
- control bits of language through trademarks.)
-
- Another example is scientific knowledge. Scientists do research and then
- publish their results. A large fraction of scientific knowledge is public
- knowledge (Ziman 1968). There are some areas of science that are not public,
- such as classified military research. It is generally argued that the most
- dynamic parts of science are those with the least secrecy. Open ideas can be
- examined, challenged, modified and improved. To turn scientific knowledge
- into a commodity on the market, as is happening with genetic engineering
- (Mackenzie et al. 1990; Weiner 1986), arguably inhibits science.
-
- Few scientists complain that they do not own the knowledge they produce.
- Indeed, they are much more likely to complain when corporations or
- governments try to control dissemination of the ideas. Most scientists
- receive a salary from a government, corporation or university. Their
- livelihoods do not depend on royalties from published work.
-
- University scientists have the greatest freedom. The main reasons they do
- research are for the intrinsic satisfaction of investigation and discovery --
- a key motivation for many of the world's great scientists -- and for
- recognition by their peers. To turn scientific knowledge into intellectual
- property would dampen the enthusiasm of many scientists for their work.
-
- Neither language nor scientific knowledge are ideal; indeed, they are often
- used for harmful purposes. It is difficult to imagine, though, how turning
- them into property could make them better.
-
- The case of science shows that vigorous intellectual activity is quite
- possible without intellectual property, and in fact that it may be vigorous
- precisely because information is not owned. But there are lots of areas that,
- unlike science, have long operated with intellectual property as a fact of
- life. What would happen without ownership of information? Many objections
- spring to mind. Here I'll deal with a few of them.
-
- Plagiarism is a great fear in the minds of many intellectual workers. It is
- often thought that intellectual property provides a protection against
- plagiarism. After all, without copyright, why couldn't someone put their name
- on your essay and publish it? Actually, copyright provides very little
- protection against plagiarism and is not a good way to deal with it (Stearns
- 1992).
-
- Plagiarism means using the ideas of others without adequate acknowledgement.
- There are several types of plagiarism. One is plagiarism of ideas: someone
- takes your original idea and, using different expression, presents it as
- their own. Copyright provides no protection at all against this form of
- plagiarism. Another type of plagiarism is word-for-word plagiarism, where
- someone takes the words you've written -- a book, an essay, a few paragraphs
- or even just a sentence -- and, with or without minor modifications, presents
- them as their own. This sort of plagiarism *is* covered by copyright --
- assuming that you hold the copyright. In many cases, copyright is held by the
- publisher, not the author. In practice, plagiarism goes on all the time, in
- various ways and degrees (Broad and Wade 1982; Mallon 1989; Posner 1988), and
- copyright law is hardly ever used against it. The most effective challenge to
- plagiarism is not legal action but publicity. At least among authors,
- plagiarism is widely condemned. To be exposed as a plagiarist is more than
- sufficient motivation for most writers to take care to avoid it.
-
- There is an even more fundamental reason why copyright provides no protection
- against plagiarism: the most common sort of plagiarism is built into social
- hierarchies. Government and corporate reports are released under the names of
- top bureaucrats who did not write them; politicians and university presidents
- give speeches written by underlings. These are examples of a pervasive
- misrepresentation of authorship in which powerful figures gain credit for the
- work of subordinates (Martin 1994). Copyright, if it has any effect at all,
- reinforces rather than challenges this sort of institutionalised plagiarism.
-
- What about all the writers, inventors and others who depend for their
- livelihood on royalties? First, it should be mentioned that only a very few
- individuals make enough money from royalties to live on. Most of the rewards
- from intellectual property go to a few big companies. But the question is
- still a serious one for those intellectual workers who depend on royalties
- and other payments related to intellectual property.
-
- The alternative in this case is some reorganisation of the economic system.
- Intellectual workers could receive a salary, just like most scientists do.
-
- Getting rid of intellectual property would reduce the incomes of a few highly
- successful creative individuals, such as author Agatha Christie, composer
- Andrew Lloyd Webber and filmmaker Steven Spielberg. Publishers could reprint
- Christie's novels without permission, theatre companies could put on Webber's
- operas whenever they wished and Spielberg's films could be copied and
- screened anywhere. Jurassic Park T-shirts, toys and trinkets could be
- produced at will. This would reduce the income of and, to some extent, the
- opportunities for artistic expression by these individuals. But there would
- be economic resources released: there would be more money available for other
- creators. Christie, Webber and Spielberg might be just as popular without
- intellectual property to channel money to them and their family enterprises.
-
- But what about the incentive to create? Without the possibility of wealth and
- fame, what would stimulate creative individuals to produce works of genius?
- Actually, most creators and innovators are motivated by their own intrinsic
- interest, not by rewards. There is a large body of evidence showing, contrary
- to popular opinion, that rewards actually reduce the quality of work (Kohn
- 1993). If the goal is better and more creative work, paying creators on a
- piecework basis, such as through royalties, is counterproductive.
-
- In a society without intellectual property, creativity is likely to thrive.
- Most of the problems that are imagined to occur if there is no intellectual
- property -- such as the exploitation of a small publisher that renounces
- copyright -- are due to economic arrangements that maintain inequality. The
- soundest foundation for a society without intellectual property is greater
- economic and political equality. This means not just equality of opportunity,
- but equality of outcomes. This does not mean uniformity and does not mean
- levelling imposed from the top: it means freedom and diversity and a
- situation where people can get what they need. There is not space to deal
- fully with this issue here, but suffice it to say that there are strong
- social and psychological arguments in favour of equality (Baker 1987; Deutsch
- 1985; Ryan 1981).
-
- STRATEGIES FOR CHANGE
-
- Challenging intellectual property is a daunting task. It is supported by many
- powerful groups: the most powerful governments and the largest corporations.
- The mass media seem fully behind intellectual property, partly because media
- monopolies would be undercut if information were more freely copied and
- partly because the most influential journalists depend on syndication rights
- for their stories. Perhaps just as important is the support for intellectual
- property from many small intellectual producers, including academics and
- freelance writers. Although the monetary returns to these intellectuals are
- seldom significant, they have been persuaded that they both need and deserve
- their small royalties. This is similar to the way that small owners of goods
- and land, such as homeowners, strongly defend the system of private property,
- whose main beneficiaries are the very wealthy who own vast enterprises based
- on many other people's labour.
-
- Another problem in developing strategies is that it makes little sense to
- challenge intellectual property in isolation. If we simply imagine
- intellectual property being abolished but the rest of the economic system
- unchanged, then many objections can be made. Challenging intellectual
- property must involve the development of methods to support today's small
- intellectual producers.
-
- An obvious way to challenge intellectual property is simply to defy it by
- reproducing protected works. From the point of view of intellectual property,
- this is called "piracy." (This is a revealing term, considering that no such
- language is used when, for example, a boss takes credit for a subordinate's
- work or when a Third World intellectual is recruited to a First World
- position (Verzola 1993).) This happens every day when people photocopy
- copyrighted articles, tape copyrighted music, or duplicate copyrighted
- software. It is precisely because illegal copying is so easy and so common
- that big governments and corporations have mounted offensives to promote
- intellectual property rights.
-
- Unfortunately, illegal copying is not a very good strategy against
- intellectual property, any more than stealing goods is a way to challenge
- ownership of physical property. Theft of any sort implicitly accepts the
- existing system of ownership. By trying to hide the copying and avoiding
- penalties, the copiers appear to accept the legitimacy of the system.
-
- Far more powerful than illicit copying is open refusal to cooperate with
- intellectual property. The methods of nonviolent action can be used here,
- including noncooperation, boycotts and setting up alternative institutions
- (Sharp 1973). By being open about the challenge, there is a much greater
- chance of focussing attention on the issues at stake and creating a dialogue.
- By being principled in opposition, and being willing to accept penalties that
- might be applied to civil disobedience to laws on intellectual property,
- there is a much greater chance of winning over third parties (Herngren 1993).
- If harsh penalties are applied to those who challenge intellectual property,
- this is likely to produce a backlash of sympathy. If mass civil disobedience
- to intellectual property laws were to occur, it would be impossible to stop.
-
- Something like that is already occurring. Because photocopying of copyrighted
- works is so common, there is seldom any attempt to enforce the law against
- small violators -- to do so would alienate too many people. Copyright
- authorities therefore seek other means of collecting revenues from
- intellectual property, such as payments by institutions based on library
- copies. There would be a much greater impact from a principled challenge to
- intellectual property, especially if some prominent people took part.
-
- Another important strategy is the promotion of non-owned information. A good
- example is public domain software, which is computer software that is made
- available free to anyone who wants it. The developers of "freeware" gain
- satisfaction out of their intellectual work and out of providing a service to
- other people.
-
- A suitable alternative to copyright is shareright. A piece of freeware might
- be accompanied by the notice, "You may reproduce this material if your
- recipients may also reproduce it." This encourages copiers but refuses any of
- them copyright.
-
- Intellectual property gives the appearance of stopping unfair appropriation
- of ideas although, as argued here, the reality is quite different. If
- intellectual property is to be challenged, people need to be reassured that
- misappropriation of ideas will not become a big problem. Therefore it is
- important to develop principles to deal with credit for intellectual work --
- even if credit is not rewarded financially. This would include guidelines for
- not misrepresenting another person's work. So-called moral rights to be
- recognised as the author of a work are relevant here.
-
- More fundamentally, it needs to be recognised that intellectual work is
- inevitably a collective process. No one has totally original ideas: ideas are
- always built on the earlier contributions of others. Furthermore,
- contributions to culture -- which makes ideas possible -- are not just
- intellectual but also practical and material, including the rearing of
- families and construction of buildings. Intellectual property is theft,
- sometimes in part from an individual creator but always from society as a
- whole.
-
- In a more cooperative society, credit for ideas would not be such a
- contentious matter. Today, there are vicious disputes between scientists over
- who should gain credit for a discovery. This is because scientists' careers
- and, more importantly, their reputations, depend on credit for ideas. In a
- society with less hierarchy and greater equality, intrinsic motivation and
- satisfaction would be the main returns from contributing to intellectual
- developments. This is quite compatible with everything that is known about
- human nature (Kohn 1990). The system of ownership encourages groups to put
- special interests above general interests. Sharing information is undoubtedly
- the most efficient way to allocate productive resources (Hahnel 1993). The
- less there is to gain from credit for ideas, the more likely people are to
- share ideas rather than worry about who deserves credit for them.
-
- Finally, it should not be imagined that getting rid of intellectual property
- is a solution to the link between information and inequality. Even without
- intellectual property, information can be controlled by powerful groups.
- National security elites use secrecy and spying to protect their operations.
- Professions use specialised training, jargon and esoteric theories, as well
- as licensing by the state, to make their work inaccessible to outsiders.
- Corporations protect many of their ideas through secrecy rather than patents.
- The law of defamation is used to punish free speech, especially criticisms of
- powerful individuals. Intellectual property is only one technique of many by
- which powerful groups control information in order to protect and expand
- their positions and wealth. Challenging intellectual property is only one
- part, though an important part, of challenging inequality.
-
- ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS: I thank Steve Fuller, Brian Rappert, Wendy Varney, Ian
- Watson and a hostile referee for The Information Society for providing
- helpful comments on a draft of this paper and Mary Cawte for tracking down
- some information. Numerous other people, through their writings,
- conversations and other activities, directly or indirectly helped make this
- work possible.
-
- REFERENCES
-
- Bagdikian, Ben. 1993. The Media Monopoly. Boston: Beacon Press, 4th edition.
-
- Baker, C. Edwin. 1989. Human Liberty and Freedom of Speech. New York: Oxford
- University Press.
-
- Baker, John. 1987. Arguing for Equality. London: Verso.
-
- Broad, William, and Nicholas Wade. 1982. Betrayers of the Truth: Fraud and
- Deceit in the Halls of Science. New York: Simon and Schuster.
-
- Deutsch, Morton. 1985. Distributive Justice: A Social-psychological
- Perspective. New Haven: Yale University Press.
-
- Drahos, Peter. June 1995. "Global property rights in information: the story
- of TRIPS at the GATT." Prometheus 13(1).
-
- Dunford, Richard. 1987. "The suppression of technology as a strategy for
- controlling resource dependence." Administrative Science Quarterly
- 32:512-525.
-
- Entman, Robert M. 1989. Democracy without Citizens: Media and the Decay of
- American Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
-
- Ewing, David W. 1977. Freedom inside the Organization: Bringing Civil
- Liberties to the Workplace. New York: Dutton.
-
- Ginsberg, Benjamin. 1986. The Captive Public: How Mass Media Promotes State
- Power. New York: Basic Books.
-
- Gleditsch, Nils Petter. April 1987. "National security and freedom of
- expression: the Scandinavian legal battles." Media Law & Practice 8:2-5.
-
- Gwyn, Robert J. 1966. "Political dissent and the free market of ideas: an
- eight-nation study." Gazette: International Journal of Mass Communication
- Studies 12:187-200.
-
- Hahnel, Robin. April 1993. "Cooperacion internacional, si! NAFTA, no!" Z
- Magazine 6(4):47-52.
-
- Hanson, Jim. 1981. "The political economy of free speech: a Marxist
- critique." Humanity and Society 5(4):370-382.
-
- Herngren, Per. 1993. Path of Resistance: The Practice of Civil Disobedience.
- Philadelphia: New Society Publishers.
-
- Hettinger, Edwin C. Winter 1989. "Justifying intellectual property."
- Philosophy and Public Affairs 18(1):31-52.
-
- Ingber, Stanley. February 1984. "The marketplace of ideas: a legitimizing
- myth." Duke Law Journal 1984(1):1-91.
-
- Kohn, Alfie. 1990. The Brighter Side of Human Nature: Altruism and Empathy in
- Everyday Life. New York: Basic Books.
-
- Kohn, Alfie. 1993. Punished by Rewards: The Trouble with Gold Stars,
- Incentive Plans, A's, Praise, and other Bribes. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
-
- Lancaster, Don. Winter 1992. "The case against patents." Whole Earth Review
- 77:86-87.
-
- Lichtenberg, Judith. Fall 1987. "Foundations and limits of freedom of the
- press." Philosophy and Public Affairs 16(4):329-355.
-
- Mackenzie, Michael, Peter Keating, and Albert Cambrosio. Winter 1990.
- "Patents and free scientific information in biotechnology: making monoclonal
- antibodies proprietary." Science, Technology, & Human Values 15(1):65-83.
-
- Mallon, Thomas. 1989. Stolen Words: Forays into the Origins and Ravages of
- Plagiarism. New York: Ticknor and Fields.
-
- Martin, Brian. Fall 1994. "Plagiarism: a misplaced emphasis." Journal of
- Information Ethics 3(2):36-47.
-
- McGaffey, Ruth. March 1972. "A critical look at the 'marketplace of ideas'."
- Speech Teacher 21(2):115-122.
-
- Mestel, Rosie. 19 February 1994. "Rich pickings for cotton's pioneers." New
- Scientist 141:13-14,
-
- Moran, Michael, and Maurice Wright (eds.). 1991. The Market and the State:
- Studies in Interdependence. London: Macmillan.
-
- Munster, George. 1982. Secrets of State: A Detailed Assessment of the Book
- They Banned. Australia: Walsh & Munster.
-
- Nelkin, Dorothy. 1984. Science as Intellectual Property: Who Controls
- Research? New York: Macmillan.
-
- Patel, Surendra J. 6 May 1989. "Intellectual property rights in the Uruguay
- Round: a disaster for the South?" Economic and Political Weekly
- 24(18):978-993.
-
- Posner, Ari. 18 April 1988. "The culture of plagiarism." The New
- Republic:19-24.
-
- Ricketson, Sam. June 1992. "New wine into old bottles: technological change
- and intellectual property rights." Prometheus 10(1):53-82.
-
- Ross, Jeffrey Ian (ed.). 1995. Controlling State Crime: An Introduction. New
- York: Garland.
-
- Ryan, William. 1981. Equality. New York: Pantheon.
-
- Sharp, Gene. 1973. The Politics of Nonviolent Action. Boston: Porter Sargent.
-
- Shiva, Vandana, and Radha Holla-Bhar. 1993. "Intellectual piracy and the neem
- tree." Ecologist 23(6):223-227.
-
- Stearns, Laurie. March 1992. "Copy wrong: plagiarism, process, property, and
- the law." California Law Review 80(2):513-553.
-
- Verzola, Roberto. January-February 1993. "The 'piracy' of intellectuals and
- intellectual property." Third World Resurgence 29/30:57-58.
-
- Weiner, Charles. February-March 1986. "Universities, professors, and patents:
- a continuing controversy." Technology Review:33-43.
-
- Wright, Steve. July-December 1991. "The new technologies of political
- repression: a case for arms control?" Philosophy and Social Action
- 17(3-4):31-62.
-
- Ziman, John. 1968. Public Knowledge: An Essay concerning the Social
- Dimensions of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
-
- ------------------------------
-
- Date: Sun, 19 Apr 1995 22:51:01 CDT
- From: CuD Moderators <cudigest@sun.soci.niu.edu>
- Subject: File 2--Cu Digest Header Info (unchanged since 19 Apr, 1995)
-
- Cu-Digest is a weekly electronic journal/newsletter. Subscriptions are
- available at no cost electronically.
-
- CuD is available as a Usenet newsgroup: comp.society.cu-digest
-
- Or, to subscribe, send a one-line message: SUB CUDIGEST your name
- Send it to LISTSERV@VMD.CSO.UIUC.EDU
- The editors may be contacted by voice (815-753-0303), fax (815-753-6302)
- or U.S. mail at: Jim Thomas, Department of Sociology, NIU, DeKalb, IL
- 60115, USA.
-
- To UNSUB, send a one-line message: UNSUB CUDIGEST
- Send it to LISTSERV@VMD.CSO.UIUC.EDU
- (NOTE: The address you unsub must correspond to your From: line)
-
- Issues of CuD can also be found in the Usenet comp.society.cu-digest
- news group; on CompuServe in DL0 and DL4 of the IBMBBS SIG, DL1 of
- LAWSIG, and DL1 of TELECOM; on GEnie in the PF*NPC RT
- libraries and in the VIRUS/SECURITY library; from America Online in
- the PC Telecom forum under "computing newsletters;"
- On Delphi in the General Discussion database of the Internet SIG;
- on RIPCO BBS (312) 528-5020 (and via Ripco on internet);
- and on Rune Stone BBS (IIRGWHQ) (203) 832-8441.
- CuD is also available via Fidonet File Request from
- 1:11/70; unlisted nodes and points welcome.
-
- EUROPE: In BELGIUM: Virtual Access BBS: +32-69-844-019 (ringdown)
- Brussels: STRATOMIC BBS +32-2-5383119 2:291/759@fidonet.org
- In ITALY: Bits against the Empire BBS: +39-464-435189
- In LUXEMBOURG: ComNet BBS: +352-466893
-
- UNITED STATES: etext.archive.umich.edu (192.131.22.8) in /pub/CuD/
- ftp.eff.org (192.88.144.4) in /pub/Publications/CuD/
- aql.gatech.edu (128.61.10.53) in /pub/eff/cud/
- world.std.com in /src/wuarchive/doc/EFF/Publications/CuD/
- wuarchive.wustl.edu in /doc/EFF/Publications/CuD/
- EUROPE: nic.funet.fi in pub/doc/cud/ (Finland)
- ftp.warwick.ac.uk in pub/cud/ (United Kingdom)
-
- JAPAN: ftp://www.rcac.tdi.co.jp/pub/mirror/CuD
-
- The most recent issues of CuD can be obtained from the
- Cu Digest WWW site at:
- URL: http://www.soci.niu.edu:80/~cudigest/
-
- COMPUTER UNDERGROUND DIGEST is an open forum dedicated to sharing
- information among computerists and to the presentation and debate of
- diverse views. CuD material may be reprinted for non-profit as long
- as the source is cited. Authors hold a presumptive copyright, and
- they should be contacted for reprint permission. It is assumed that
- non-personal mail to the moderators may be reprinted unless otherwise
- specified. Readers are encouraged to submit reasoned articles
- relating to computer culture and communication. Articles are
- preferred to short responses. Please avoid quoting previous posts
- unless absolutely necessary.
-
- DISCLAIMER: The views represented herein do not necessarily represent
- the views of the moderators. Digest contributors assume all
- responsibility for ensuring that articles submitted do not
- violate copyright protections.
-
- ------------------------------
-
- End of Computer Underground Digest #7.51
- ************************************
-
-