home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Path: sparky!uunet!mtnmath!paul
- From: paul@mtnmath.UUCP (Paul Budnik)
- Newsgroups: sci.physics
- Subject: Re: The instantaneous transfer of information in QM calculations
- Message-ID: <490@mtnmath.UUCP>
- Date: 12 Jan 93 18:02:50 GMT
- References: <1993Jan10.164016.16419@cs.wayne.edu> <1993Jan12.011324.3713@cs.wayne.edu>
- Organization: Mountain Math Software, P. O. Box 2124, Saratoga. CA 95070
- Lines: 105
-
- In article <1993Jan12.011324.3713@cs.wayne.edu>, atems@igor.physics.wayne.edu (Dale Atems) writes:
- > [...]
- > Please show me where. In this case QM predicts a certain value for the
- > quantity P(a,b) = < (S(1,a) S(2,b) >, this is the expectation value
- > for the product of the spin components in a singlet pair. What you
- > need to predict is P(a,b), P(a,c), and P(b,c). For some choices of the
- > unit vectors a,b,c, the QM predictions (using only the linear theory)
- > violate Bell's inequality.
-
- I make the point *again* you are not testing Bell's inequality unless you
- have a controllable device. Correlations by themselves can violate the
- mathematical relationship, but this relationship is only predicted to
- hold under certain conditions. It is only the correlation between a settable
- experimental parameter and observations affected by that parameter that
- are predicted to hold in Bell's theorem. You can generate any correlation
- function you choose using local processes. This will not violate Bell's
- inequality under the conditions in which that inequality is predicted to
- hold.
-
- It is nonetheless true that the standard QM calculations to predict P(a,b)
- do involve collapse and do involve the nonlocal transfer of information.
- An experiment of this type cannot provide a conclusive demonstration that
- locality is violated, but the predictions of quantum mechanics still imply
- that it is. When you observe the spin at one location you collapse the wave
- function in accord with that observation. You use the results of this
- projection operation to compute the probability for the second observation.
- The probability for the second observation is dependent on the other
- observation and that dependence requires that wave function you use for
- the calculation be affected by the first observation.
-
- You cannot assume that the spin was determined at the time the particles
- separated. If that were the case you could use a linear evolution of the
- wave function to compute the probabilities. The spin is only determined
- when it is observed. The observation *changes* the singlet state wave
- function (it does not simply reveal additional information about it,
- it *changes* the function) and this change must be taken into account
- when computing the probability of a particular observation on the particle
- paired with the one you observed.
-
- >
- > >What is crucial about Bell's inequality is that
- > >the observation at one site was *affected* by the *measurement* made
- > >at the other site.
- >
- > This cannot be said with certainty. The most one can say, I believe,
- > is that the correlations are inconsistent with the assumptions that all
- > the observables are fixed before measurement, *and* that no
- > observation affected the outcome of a distant measurement. The
- > violations of Bell's inequality mean that at least one of these
- > assumptions is incorrect.
-
- I claim they must *both* be false. If the observables were determined
- before measurement you cannot get a violation of Bell's inequality even
- with instantaneous transmission of information. What use would such
- information transfer be since you are only observing what has already
- been predetermined long ago.
-
- >[...]
- > >To get the QM prediction you have
- > >to use more then the assumption that the two particles are in a singlet
- > >state.
- >
- > No, I believe this is all you need.
-
- The singlet state wave function before any observation is different
- that the singlet state wave function after observing one of the
- two particles. If you use the former to compute the probability densitys
- for detecting *both* particles you will get the wrong answer.
-
- > [...]
- > I don't use the probability density for a detection at all. Everything
- > is expressed in terms of average values of products of spin
- > components. I suspect we are having trouble communicating because of
- > the difference in experimental setups -- in the photon experiment, the
- > detection of a photon that has passed through a polarizer means that
- > it was "found" to be in a particular linear polarization state.
-
- Of course you can use shorthand techniques to compute these results.
- However, in a discussion of this sort, you need to go to the original theory
- and understand how those techniques are derived from that theory. I think
- if you do this exercise you will see the need for collapse in that derivation.
-
- > Yes, that is the point! If the assumptions behind Bell's proof are
- > correct, you *shouldn't* see his inequality violated. If you do even
- > though no subluminal signal could have influenced the results, then
- > either you are dealing with superluminal signals -- instantaneous
- > transfer of information in some frame -- or else it is not the case
- > that all spin components were determined when the state was prepared.
-
- As I explained earlier it is not a case of either but a case of both.
- Eberhard's derivation of Bell's theorem makes no reference to hidden
- variable theorys or predetermined states. It only talks about an
- experimental manipulation instantaneously influencing an experimental
- observation in a nonlocal way. See "Bell's Theorem without Hidden
- Variables", P. H. Eberhard, Il Nuovo Cimento, 38 B 1, p 75, (1977).
-
- > [...]
- > In QM it is not information transfer at all. The correlations are
- > inconsistent only with assumptions that the standard interpretation of
- > QM denies.
-
- Please read Eberhard's proof. If you still believe this I will be extremely
- interrested in hearing you explain why.
-
- Paul Budnik
-