home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Newsgroups: sci.physics
- Path: sparky!uunet!well!sarfatti
- From: sarfatti@well.sf.ca.us (Jack Sarfatti)
- Subject: More Super Debate! Sarfatti vs. Svetlichny
- Message-ID: <BxA8Lq.1u4@well.sf.ca.us>
- Sender: news@well.sf.ca.us
- Organization: Whole Earth 'Lectronic Link
- Date: Fri, 6 Nov 1992 06:56:13 GMT
- Lines: 217
-
-
- Let experiment decide! This is getting Medieval - how many phases can
- land on the head of a photo-sensitive pin and will they all cancel each
- other out?
-
- With Sarfatti's comments:
- From: svetlich@math.rutgers.edu (George Svetlichny)
- Newsgroups: sci.physics,alt.sci.physics.new-theories
- Subject: No FTL signal proofs still good.
- Summary: Sarfatti's objections to no FTL signal proofs do not stand.
- Keywords: superluminal, signal, quantum, correlation, Heisenberg,
- uncertainty
- Date: 5 Nov 92 17:47:41 GMT
- Followup-To: sci.physics
- Organization: Rutgers Univ., New Brunswick, N.J.
- Lines: 135
-
- Sarfatti's argument against the validity of the contention that standard
- quantum mechanics (SQM) forbids superluminal quantum-correlation signals
- is apparently based on two allegations:
-
- 1. Besides dynamical equations there are boundary conditions and
- Sarfatti uses novel boundary conditions.
-
- Sarfatti replies."No I have not used 'novel' conditions unless Feynman's
- sum over histories picture of sqm is 'novel."
-
- 2. Commuting observables are nevertheless incompatible due to state
- entanglement as was shown by Schroedinger in 1930 and by de la Torre in
- the past two years.
-
- Neither of these allegations stand up as an argument for SQM implying
- superluminal signals.
-
- Sarfatti replies: "I have made an explicit computation showing
- communication between commuting observables in sqm. 2 does show that the
- raison d'etre for using the commutativity criterion is false."
-
- In relation to the first one should call attention to the fact that SQM
- _does_ impose restrictions on boundary conditions, usually through
- precise domain requirements on unbounded operators in hilbert space.
- Such requirements are usually to the effect that any putative operator
- (generally differential) that is to represent an observable should be
- essentially self adjoint, and this translates itself into boundary
- conditions on the vectors in its domain. Imposing any other "novel"
- boundary conditions is as much a deviation from SQM as is using
- non-unitary evolution (and in particular cases can amount to the same
- thing).
-
- More to the point though is that considerations of evolution for the
- no-signal theorem is secondary. The theorem is basically a consequence
- of two main assumptions:
-
- a) The mean value of any observable is given as a matrix element
- (F,AF) of a self-adjoint operator A in the state F.
-
- b) Operators corresponding to observations carried out at space-like
- separation commute.
-
- Now an observation can be carried out by a complex arrangement of
- physical object which may interact among themselves and with the system
- being observed. The functioning of such an arrangement can then be
- described by appropriate dynamical laws, evolution equations, boundary
- conditions, etc. If these do not follow SQM rules one may end up with an
- arrangement that doesn't satisfy a) above. But then such an arrangement
- by definition does not realize a SQM observable. The role of evolution
- in the no-signal theorem is thus indirect and the argument does not
- essentially depend on it. One just has to ask if the arrangements on
- both sides of Sarfatti's experiment satisfy a) above or not. If not, SQM
- has been abandoned, if yes, all arguments concerning evolution and
- boundary conditions are irrelevant.
-
- If Sarfatti admits that his arrangements satisfy a) he must now face b).
- Since he apparently doesn't deny this, the no-signal theorem follows and
- his device can't work.
-
- Well, what about Schroedinger and de la Torre? Sarfatti doesn't supply us
- with references and I've not located Schroedinger's argument, but for
- de la Torre (where one finds some mention of Schroedinger's expression)
- he probably means:
-
- A. C. del la Torre, P. Catuogno and S. Ferrando
-
- "Uncertainty and nonseparability"
- Found. Phys. Lett. 2, 235 (89)
-
- and
-
- "Nonseparability and noncommutativity in quantum systems"
- Found. Phys. Lett. 4, 49 (1991)
-
- Now these papers are certainly within the realm of SQM and though the
- authors seem to derive some of their motivation from philosophical
- considerations usually found in hidden-variable arguments, their
- calculations are within SQM. Their calculation is nothing more than to
- derive what appears to be a Heisenberg-type uncertainty relation for
- commuting observables in a given state, that is if A, B are quantum
- mechanical observables (commuting or not) then in a state F one can
- derive that
-
- Delta A Delta B >= |T(A,B,F)|
-
- where Delta A is the root mean square of the observed values of A in F
- and similarly for B. (Delta A)^2 = (F, A^2F) - (F, AF)^2, and T(A,B,F)
- = (F, ABF)-(F, AF)(F, BF).
-
- This is nothing more than the Cauchy Schwartz inequality. Similarly if X
- and Y are two _classical_ random variables then
-
- s(X)s(Y) >= |C(X,Y)|
-
- where s(X) is the standard deviation of X, likewise for Y. and C(X, Y)
- is the covariance. Thus _classical_ random variables satisfy (shall we
- say it?) a Heisenberg-type inequality.
-
- De la Torre et al. have a curious phrase in their second paper:
-
- "In the last section we have shown that there are physical states where
- commuting observables are incompatible due to the nonseparability or
- non-PI." (non-PI translates to T(A, B, F) not vanishing). This is a very
- strange idea of incompatibility. They seem to feel a Heisenberg-type
- inequality implies incompatibility. They missed a few essential points
- about Heisenberg uncertainty relations (like being able to give a
- state-independent lower bound to the right hand side).
-
- Sarfatti asks: "In terms of communication, why do we need a 'state-
- independent lower bound'? My assertion is that the connection signal is
- state-dependent - one needs a special kind of entanglement to do the job."
-
- One cannot derive from their inequality for commuting observables the same
- type of conclusions that one derives from the Heisenberg uncertainty
- relations.
-
- Sarfatti replies: "I don't see why not. And your analogy that follows is
- not relevant I believe."
-
- If one could, all statisticians would have to study quantum mechanics
- as classical random variable would then behave like quantum
- observables.. For instance, knowing that incidence of lung cancer and
- smoking are correlated one deduces an a-priori inequality relating the
- standard deviations of the number of cigarettes smoked and of the
- severity of lung lesions, making their product bounded below by the
- modulus of the covariance. Does does this means these two variables are
- incompatible? Does it mean reducing the one number (holding smoking to
- zero, hence zero standard deviation) will make the other standard
- deviation (severity of lung lesions) go infinite?
-
- Sarfatti replies: "Maybe not, but in the quantum case I show by explicit
- computation that it does. I mean probability of detection for ideal
- transmitter counter is 1 and the complementary "fringe" detection
- probabilities for the two receiver counters are
-
- [1 + sin(2theta)cos (phi)]/2 and [1 - sin(2theta)cos (phi)]/2
-
- respectively. If there is a classical probability distribution for phi
- I don't like <cos(phi)> = 0, and there may be a way to avoid it by clever
- phase compensation, but even if it is true one still gets receiver photo-
- current fluctuations proportional to sin(2theta) where theta is a nonlocal
- un-hidden parameter (global boundary condition shift) that can be
- manipulated from the distant transmitter to shift the local receiver
- currents - and I claim that this is sqm in the Feynman history sense."
-
- PS "Your use of "statistics" below is clever and well written but not
- convincing - but to those who wish to keep the faith of retarded physics it
- may be a convincing placebo."
-
-
- Do people with perfect lungs invariably smoke a widely varying number of
- cigarettes a day?
-
- The cited results (and probably Schroedinger's as well) have nothing to
- do with superluminal signals as the same reasoning would apply to states
- and experimental arrangements conforming to Bell's inequalities for
- which a common cause explanation for the correlations can be given, and
- no one believes that common-cause correlations can be used for
- superluminal signals. Otherwise one could build a superluminal telegraph
- utilizing a "source" that randomly picks matched pairs of socks and
- sends each one in opposite directions. There would be an observer
- catching one of the socks, and by analyzing it, would determine if the
- space-like separated observer was looking at the color or at the
- weave-pattern of the other mate. If a state-dependent seemingly
- Heisenberg-like inequality was all that was needed to send signals, this
- would work.
-
- Sarfatti's final comment:"Look I gave an explicit model. Transmitter is
- calcite. Ordinary beam passes half-wave plate, then extraordinary and
- ordinary beams brought together at a single finite area counter. I have
- shown elsewhere how I get above-cited results."
-
- --
- George Svetlichny /\ On leave from:
- Department of Mathematics /***| Departamento de Matematica
- Hill Center, Rutgers University /****| Pontificia Universidade
- Catolica
- New Brunswick, 08903 NJ /*****| Rio de Janeiro, Brazil
-
- One more "final" comment by Sarfatti: I start with standard photon pair
- state. I then use local unitary evolutions at the transmitter to distort
- it - many half-wave plate to bring the two linear polarizations into
- alignment. Then I combine then two beams into one counter and compute
- the non-unitary collapse (i.e. the expectation value of projection
- operator for photon to hit same counter, only one counter not two on
- transmitter side) - provided that there is no superselection rule
- forbitting coherence between extraordinary and rotated ordinary beams (no
- such rule in Stern Gerlach for neutrons or electrons) then the effect
- I predict will happen. It's all like the double slit experiment. The
- extraordinary and ordinary paths of the transmitter photon is like the
- ordinary photon passing one slit or another. However, it is the twin
- receiver photon that behaves like the ordinary photon hitting the screen.
- Quantum action at a distance through the entangled connection makes the
- receiver photon show the complementary fringes - local probabilities add
- up to 1 on both sides! The fringes are not found at the transmitter side.
- They are stolen by the receiver via the connection. The connection signal is
- a phase interference or "fringe" signal. It's a "teleportation" of fringe
- information from transmitter to receiver. Think physically guys. I can
- visualize all this. It's very physical. It's very beautiful - and it
- may even be true!
-