home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Xref: sparky can.general:5305 can.politics:9491 soc.culture.canada:8392
- Path: sparky!uunet!usc!zaphod.mps.ohio-state.edu!sol.ctr.columbia.edu!destroyer!cs.ubc.ca!unixg.ubc.ca!ramsay
- From: ramsay@unixg.ubc.ca (Keith Ramsay)
- Newsgroups: can.general,can.politics,soc.culture.canada
- Subject: Re: Voting Systems (was Re: Proportional representation)
- Date: 8 Nov 1992 23:02:37 GMT
- Organization: University of British Columbia, Vancouver, B.C., Canada
- Lines: 54
- Message-ID: <1dk6adINN5jb@iskut.ucs.ubc.ca>
- References: <1992Nov7.205857.8656@thunder.mcrcim.mcgill.edu> <1dhqfrINNrjv@iskut.ucs.ubc.ca> <1992Nov8.074732.7435@ee.ubc.ca>
- NNTP-Posting-Host: unixg.ubc.ca
-
- In article <1992Nov8.074732.7435@ee.ubc.ca> jmorriso@ee.ubc.ca
- (John Paul Morrison) writes:
- [Regarding the Arrow impossibility theorem:]
- >I would like to see how this following system is affected. I believe
- >that the theorem you mention can't apply in this case.
- [...]
- >This is similar to the way shareholders elect a board (but not really,
- >so don't bother picking on this point).
- >
- >1. A voter can only vote for one person, no prioritizing
- >2. The candidate is elected if he gets at least one vote.
- >3. The candidate is actually a delegate, so in parliament, he or she
- > represents as many votes as they received.
-
- For this voting system the "alternatives" being chosen from, i.e., the
- possible outcomes of the vote, include all the possible ways of
- selecting a group of delegates, with weights assigned to them (which
- total up to the number of voters). It is clearly not allowed for
- voters to arrange all of these (zillions of) possibilities in priority
- order.
-
- There's no way to express the preference, for instance, of those who
- might mainly want some kind of coherence and consensus of purpose in
- the parliament, for efficiency, and aren't as concerned about getting
- their own first choice of representative into it.
-
- It also fails another condition of the theorem, in that it is possible
- for a person to cause an option A to be selected instead of an option
- B, by deciding to try to get C instead of D. Suppose there are a
- number of us who'd like to vote for Smith, but for whatever reason
- we'd rather she not have too much power. If, however, she already has
- sufficient votes, then we'd rather vote for Jones.
-
- Let A, B, C, and D be possible compositions of the legislature, where
- A differs from B only by Smith getting some of the votes Jones got in
- case B, and likewise for C and D, where A and B are alternatives in
- which Smith gets enormous power, and C and D are alternatives in which
- Smith gets either a modest amount or none at all. The condition
- described by the theorem, requiring that changing preferences between
- A and B will not affect whether C or D is chosen, is violated by this
- voting system. By trying to ensure Smith gets a modicum of influence,
- we could end up giving her more than we had wanted, or conversely.
-
- The conditions about "independence of preferences" are in some sense
- the stiffest constraints placed by the theorem, and are often
- violated. It is often possible for it to be the case that if you
- prefer A to B to C, you are well advised to vote as if you prefer B
- most of all, so as to make sure that B rather than C occurs. This
- "sophistical voting" is what the Arrow conditions are formulated to
- preclude, and the upshot is that there always is a price paid for
- avoiding it.
-
- Keith Ramsay
- ramsay@unixg.ubc.ca
-