home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Path: sparky!uunet!pipex!doc.ic.ac.uk!uknet!comlab.ox.ac.uk!mbeattie
- From: mbeattie@black.ox.ac.uk (Malcolm Beattie)
- Newsgroups: sci.math
- Subject: Re: Alephs again
- Message-ID: <1993Jan22.135210.9175@black.ox.ac.uk>
- Date: 22 Jan 93 13:52:10 GMT
- References: <1993Jan19.082655.6274@dxcern.cern.ch> <1jh2epINN15k@gap.caltech.edu> <1993Jan20.155553.19920@cadkey.com>
- Organization: Oxford University Computing Service, 13 Banbury Rd, Oxford, U
- Lines: 63
- Originator: mbeattie@black
-
- In article <1993Jan20.155553.19920@cadkey.com> dennis@cadkey.com (Dennis Paul Himes) writes:
- >In article <1jh2epINN15k@gap.caltech.edu> allenk@ugcs.caltech.edu (Allen Knutson) writes:
- >>ydavid@dxds04.cern.ch (David Yann) greets us, and asks a bunch of
- >>set-theory questions. I'll state at the beginning: if one has the
- >>Axiom of Choice, much cardinal arithmetic becomes trivial.
- >>Without it, most things are hard (a countable union of countable
- >>sets can be uncountable, for instance).
- >>
- > Is this true? What is wrong with the following enumeration?
- > Let f(i,j) be the i^th element of the j^th set, both indices starting
- >at zero. Enumerate the union as follows:
- >n = 0;
- >for (i0 = 0; ; ++i0) {
- > for (i1 = 0; i1 <= i0; ++i1) {
- > enumeration[n++] = f (i1, i0 - i1);
- > }
- >}
- > Or, for those of you who don't know C,
- >f (0, 0),
- >f (0, 1), f (1, 0),
- >f (0, 2), f (1, 1), f (2, 0),
- >f (0, 3), f (1, 2), f (2, 1), f (3, 0),
- >etc.
- > Some work would have to be done to eliminate duplicates, but I don't
- >see how this depends on AC or how this would not apply to any countable
- >union of countable sets.
-
- Here is the problem: what do you mean by *the* $i$th
- of *the* $j$th set?
- The explanation is going to hinge on the difference
- between a set being _countable_ and a set being _counted_.
- For a set to be _countable_ just tells us that there _exists_
- some bijection with \omega; whereas a set being _counted_ (*)
- means that we are _given_ such a bijection.
-
- You may well be able to fill in the details for yourself now,
- but if not, let's start from scratch.
- Let {A_j | j \in J} be a family of countable sets such that
- J is countable too.
- Certainly, we can pick and fix a bijection of J with \omega
- (there is only one `choice' to make) and use this bijection
- to enumerate the family of A_j as A_1, A_2, A_3, ...
- Now we have an infinite number of A_j, each of which is
- countable. Howeverm, there is no _given_ bijection of each
- A_j with \omega. This means that to enumerate each A_j
- as {a_j1, a_j2, a_j3, ...} we have to _pick_ a bijection
- of that A_j with \omega. This involves an infinite number
- of choices (i.e. one for each j \in J) and cannot be done
- without some form of Choice axiom.
- I think one can get by with an axiom of `countable choice'
- but I'm not sure.
-
- (*) The use of the word `counted' isn't very common, but it
- makes a useful distinction here which helps to explain things.
- I can't remember where I saw the distinction presented this way.
-
- --Malcolm
-
- --
- Malcolm Beattie <mbeattie@black.ox.ac.uk> | I'm not a kernel hacker
- Oxford University Computing Services | I'm a kernel hacker's mate
- 13 Banbury Road, Oxford, OX2 6NN (U.K.) | And I'm only hacking kernels
- Tel: +44 865 273232 Fax: +44 865 273275 | 'Cos the kernel hacker's late
-