home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Comments: Gated by NETNEWS@AUVM.AMERICAN.EDU
- Path: sparky!uunet!zaphod.mps.ohio-state.edu!howland.reston.ans.net!paladin.american.edu!auvm!NIU.BITNET!P30GDS1
- Message-ID: <QUALRS-L%93010822454781@UGA.CC.UGA.EDU>
- Newsgroups: bit.listserv.qualrs-l
- Date: Fri, 8 Jan 1993 21:44:00 CST
- Sender: Qualitative Research for the Human Sciences <QUALRS-L@UGA.BITNET>
- From: Gary Shank <P30GDS1@NIU.BITNET>
- Subject: Re: reality check?
- Lines: 667
-
- Qualitative Research? Quantitative Research? WhatUs the Problem?
- Resolving the Dilemma via a Postconstructivist Approach
-
-
- Gary Shank Northern Illinois University
-
- Introduction
-
- The Rqualitative vs quantitativeS debate has been part of the fabric of
- educational research for some time. ( cf. Smith, 1983; Gage, 1989;
- Rizo, 1991; Salomon, 1991 for various discussions of the debate) At
- stake in this debate is the issue of whether two worldviews of
- research can coexist, or if one has to eventually either incorporate or
- discredit the other.
- In this paper, I would like to take a slightly different turn. I would like
- to start by examining what is one of the most important qualitative
- turns in educational research, namely the constructivist stance. Most
- issues that surface in an examination of constructivism are actually
- metonymous to issues that are found in the larger qualitative context,
- and, given the prominence of constructivism in educational technology
- research, an analysis of constructivism per se should be concretely
- fruitful to an educational technology audience. By grounding
- constructivism in the larger qualitative tradition and by contrasting it
- with positivism, (arguably the philosophical basis for most
- quantitative research in education; cf. Schrag (1992) for a recent
- defense of positivism in educational research) I would like to show
- that the Rqualitative vs quantitativeS debate, played out here in
- concrete terms as a constructivist-positivist argument, is actually an
- example of a much deeper and long-standing conflict of issues in the
- history of science. Finally, I would like to use this discussion as a
- scaffold to address the original question. I will hopefully demonstrate
- that the flaw with most current qualitative methods and theoretical
- positions in educational research, including constructivism, is that
- they suffer from a lack of vision, such that these theories and methods
- do not stand on their own and make sense on their own terms. In an
- attempt to ground a truly unique vision, I would like to be the first to
- pose a postconstructivist model for educational research and practice.
-
- Constructivism and Educational Technology Research
-
- Let me start off by saying that some of my best friends are
- constructivists. I also would like to acknowledge that constructivism
- draws much of its energy from the same recent historical trends that
- have come to produce what we consider to be mainstream qualitative
- research in education, including holistic ethnography, symbolic
- interactionism, cultural anthropology, and the like. (cf. Jacob, 1987,
- for a review of these trends) However, I think it is important for us to
- realize that constructivism assumes certain stated and unstated
- assumptions that ground it very clearly to certain trends of thought,
- and that unreflectively accepting the basic tenets of these trends can
- lead us into some troubling consequences.
- Merrill (1991) summarizes constructivism as being based on the
- following assumptions; 1) knowledge is constructed by the learner, 2)
- learning is a personal interpretation of experience, 3) learning is
- active, 4) learning is collaborative, 5) learning is situated in real
- world contexts, and 6) assessment of learning is integrated within the
- learning context itself. (p. 46) Duffy & Jonassen (1991) acknowledge
- that Rconstructivism provides an alternative epistemological baseS (p.
- 8) for research in educational technology. They cite recent work in
- situated cognition as the basis for much of constructivist theory, (cf.
- Brown, Collins & Duguid, 1989 for a statement of the basic principles
- of situated cognition in educational research) contrasting such
- theoretical work against what Lakoff & Johnson (1980) called the
- RObjectivistS tradition. When we look at the Objectivist tradition, we
- find that it is really what we have come to call the positivist position
- in research. Therefore, it is no surprise that constructivism is
- deliberately anti-positivistic in its outlook.
- While constructivism appears to differ from older, behavioristic
- models of research, it seems to be perfectly attuned to more current
- directions in psychology. For instance, Perkins (1991) explicitly links
- constructivism with information processing theory by noting:
-
- ...information processing models have spawned the computer model of
- the mind as an information processor. Constructivism has added that
- this information processor must be seen as not just shuffling data, but
- wielding it flexibly during learning - making hypotheses, testing
- tentative interpretations, and so on. (p. 21)
-
- By linking information processing and constructivism, Perkins brings
- together contemporary cognitive theory and constructivist theory. This
- is an important step, because it anchors constructivism within the
- mainstream of scientific thought in the human sciences. Spiro, et al
- (1991) continue this thread, by further linking constructivism with
- schema theory. With its insistence on being more free-form and less
- centralized, constructivist theory also has a natural affinity to
- theoretical work in connectionism, (Bereiter, 1991) hypermedia,
- (Tolhurst, 1992) and multimedia. (Dede, 1992) On a practical
- educational level, Bagley & Hunter (1992) argue that constructivism is
- the RglueS that can hold together the combination of technological
- innovation and restructuring needed in our school systems.
- All else aside, the debate about constructivism centers on whether we
- are willing to take a positivist stance toward research in education as
- was done in the past, or whether we need a new position. In order to
- make such a decision, the researcher should be aware of what a
- position entails, and where it came from. Therefore, we need to focus
- on where constructivist ideas come from, and why they have such
- purchase on the imagination of researchers in education and other
- human sciences.
-
- The Roots of Constructivism
-
- What are the basic tenets of constructivism? Cole (1992) claims that
- Rsocial negotiation of meaningS and Rcritical argumentationS (p. 27)
- are the keystones to the constructivist approach. Cunningham (1991) in
- his neo-Galilean dialogue between a constructivist and a positivist, has
- RSalviatiS define constructivism thusly:
-
- Constructivism holds that learning is a process of building up
- structures of experience. Learners do not transfer knowledge from the
- external world to their memories; rather, they create interpretations
- of the world based on their past experiences and their interactions in
- the world. How someone construes the world, their existing metaphors,
- is at least as powerful a factor influencing what what is learned as any
- characteristic of that world. Some would even argue that knowledge
- that is incompatible with or unaccounted for in an individualUs
- interpretation cannot be learned. (p. 13)
-
- These ideas are quite different from the notions that have guided
- educational research through most of the twentieth century. What are
- their historical roots? All talk of cognitive theory and methodology
- aside, it is reasonable to claim that constructivism is basically
- grounded in the work of three contemporary philosophers of inquiry
- methodology - Richard Rorty, Nelson Goodman, and Paul Feyerabend.
- Richard Rorty, with his neo-pragmatism, (Rorty, 1982; Trimbur & Holt,
- 1992) is probably the most influential person in the philosophy of
- science today, as well as being the heir apparent to KuhnUs
- tremendously important theorizing on the role of paradigms and
- paradigm shifting in scientific research. Rorty pushes the idea of the
- paradigm shift to the extreme with his model of narrative philosophy.
- In narrative philosophy:
-
- Rorty shifts the terms from a search for method to a strategy of
- historicization. He urges us to look at philosophical discourse as
- language-in-action - not a privileged perspective that holds out the
- hope of finally moving from speculation to science but simply the
- stories philosophers tell each other.... To historicize philosophy in this
- way...means we will no longer possess a universal measure by which to
- judge knowledge claims and the accuracy with which they represent
- reality.... To recognize that philosophy is no more and no less than its
- own narratives is to recognize that we will always get the past that
- we deserve - not a final definitive version of philosophical problems
- and issues but the version our present situations calls up. We will
- have what was there all along - ourselves, our common activities, our
- attempts to cope with reality. And we will be no worse for our
- judgements. It is just that our judgements will no longer be concerned
- with what is true and accurate according to some extrahistorical
- criteria. (Trimbur & Holt,1992: 75)
-
- Nelson GoodmanUs Ways of Worldmaking (1978) reads like a manifesto
- for the constructivist movement:
-
- Truth, far from being a solemn and severe master, is a docile and
- obedient servant. The scientist who supposes that he is single-
- mindedly dedicated to the search for truth deceives himself. He is
- unconcerned with the trivial truths he could grind out endlessly.... He
- seeks system, simplicity and scope; and when satisfied on these scores
- he as much decrees as discovers the laws he sets forth, as much
- designs as discerns the patterns he delineates.... Truth, moreover,
- pertains solely to what is said, and literal truth to what is said
- literally. We have seen, though, that worlds are made not only by what
- is said literally but also by what is said metaphorically.... (p. 18)
-
- Paul FeyerabendUs (1975) self-styled anarchistic emphasis on the
- practice of science as opposed to theorizing also strikes a fundamental
- chord in the constructivist model:
-
- It is clear, then, that the idea of a fixed method, or of a fixed theory of
- rationality, rests on too naive a view of man and his social
- surroundings. To those who look at the rich material provided by
- history, and who are not intent on impoverishing it in order to please
- their lower instincts, their craving for intellectual security in the
- form of clarity, precision, TobjectivityU, TtruthU, it will become clear
- that there is only one principle that can be defended in all
- circumstances and in all stages of human development. It is the
- principle: anything goes. ( P. 28, italics his).
-
- Guba (1992) explicitly links Feyerabend to his project of relativism
- which Guba says R ...is an essential element in defining the ontological
- and epistemological presuppositions of the constructivist inquiry
- paradigm of which I am a proponent.S (p. 17) Eisner, (1992) whose
- critical version of qualitative methodology is akin to GubaUs model of
- constructivism, draws heavily on Rorty and Goodman in his attempt to
- critique objectivity in a postpositivist frame. Therefore, we can
- assume that Rorty, Goodman, and Feyerabend are central figures in the
- emerging constructivist-qualitative paradigm developing and growing
- within educational research. What are the common issues that unite
- these three foundational constructivist thinkers , and how can we
- examine those issues to help understand the basic tenets of
- constructivist thinking? Essentially, Rorty, Goodman, and Feyerabend
- all share a concern for the historical side to human inquiry, and this is
- no accident. This is because all three of them see themselves as
- members of the pragmatist tradition, a tradition that Pepper (1942), in
- his review of metaphysical positions, labeled RcontextualismS.
- Contextualism, furthermore, took its root metaphor from the idea of
- the historical event. Pragmatism has always looked to the context of
- practice, in historical and cultural terms, as the basis for resolving
- issues of meaning. (cf. House, 1991; Cherryholmes, 1992; House, 1992
- for a discussion of the role of pragmatism vs realism in scientific
- inquiry in educational research) Therefore, we can conclude that
- constructivism, as articulated in educational research settings, is a
- species of pragmatism. This link to pragmatism will ironically provide
- us with the means to move from constructivism to postconstructivism,
- since we will make that move by linking the concerns expressed in
- constructivism to the ideas of the philosophers who formulated
- pragmatism in the first place.
-
- Steps toward a Postconstructivist Model
-
- The path to a postconstructivist model of educational research is based
- on the split within pragmatism that has shaped that philosophical
- discipline from its outset. Pragmatism is a movement with two
- founders - an actual founder (C.S. Peirce) and an expedient founder
- (William James). Many of the problems that arise in pragmatism are
- based on the fact that the ideas of the actual founder and the expedient
- founder are different in important ways.
- Let us start with the expedient founder of pragmatism - William
- James. In 1898, in a lecture at the University of California, James
- stated his version of pragmatism in such a way that the ideas caught
- the imagination of the American intellectual community for decades to
- come. Even though James was careful to acknowledge that his good
- friend, Charles Peirce, was the founder of pragmatism, few people
- actually looked at PeirceUs ideas. Instead, they followed JamesUs dicta.
- JamesUs version of pragmatism is fairly simple. He held that
- pragmatism was a means for determining the truth of certain claims.
- That method works as follows (James, 1948):
- RGrant an idea or belief to be true,S it says, Rwhat concrete difference
- will its being true make in any oneUs actual life? How will the truth be
- realized? What experiences will be different from those which would
- obtain if the belief were false? What, in short, is the truthUs cash-
- value in experiential terms?S The moment pragmatism asks this
- question, it sees the answer: True ideas are those that we can
- assimilate, validate, corroborate and verify.
- False ideas are those we cannot. That is the practical difference it
- makes for us to have true ideas; that, therefore, is the meaning of
- truth, for that is all that truth is known- as. (pp.160-161; italics his)
- Now, let us compare JamesUs maxim on the pragmatic notion of truth
- with the Pragmatic Maxim. This Maxim, first published in 1878 and
- pretty much ignored thereafter, is PeirceUs definition of pragmatism
- (Peirce, 1955):
-
- Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings,
- we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception
- of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object. (p. 31)
-
- Granting that the above quote is hard to understand, let us look at a
- passage where Peirce explicates his maxim:
-
- ...the whole meaning of an intellectual predicate is that certain kinds
- of events would happen, once in so often, in the course of experience,
- under certain kinds of existential conditions - provided it can be
- proved to be true. ( p. 273; italics his)
-
- And elsewhere:
-
- But of the myriads of forms into which a proposition may be
- translated, what is that one which may be called its very meaning? It
- is... that form in which the proposition becomes applicable to human
- conduct, not in these or those special circumstances, nor when one
- entertains this or that special design, but that form which is most
- directly applicable to self-control under every situation, and to every
- purpose. That is why he locates the meaning in future-time; for future
- conduct is the only conduct that is subject to self-control. (p. 261)
-
- Finally, let us turn to MurphyUs (1990) paraphrase of PeirceUs
- pragmatic maxim, which Murphy calls PeirceUs Principle of Meaning:
- If one can define accurately all the criteria governing uses to which a
- predicate can be put, one will have therein a complete definition of the
- meaning of what it predicates. (p. 46)
-
- Compare this now with MurphyUs (1990) paraphrase of JamesUs theory
- of truth:
- What is true in our way of thinking is the production of beliefs that
- prove themselves to be good, and good for definite, assignable reasons.
- (p. 57)
-
- Peirce and James mean two very different things by pragmatism.
- Peirce saw the Pragmatic Maxim as a way of determining the logical
- nature and consequences of certain beliefs in terms of the practical
- consequences of holding those beliefs. James, on the other hand, saw
- the Pragmatic Maxim as a method of determining the truth of a given
- proposition. For Peirce, belief claims were contextual and provisional,
- yet truth claims were more general and logically accessible. For
- James, truth claims, not just meaning claims, were provisional and
- contextual. Because Peirce held that there can be truth over and above
- what we might think to be true, he is ultimately a realist. Since James
- always grounds truth claims in contextualist activities, he is
- ultimately a relativist. And the gap between the two is quite vast.
- The pragmatism that informs Rorty, Goodman, and Feyerabend, and thus
- ultimately the constructivists, is derived from James. For instance,
- Rorty (1982) turns explicitly to James to make the following points
- about JamesUs view of truth:
-
- JamesUs point was that there is nothing deeper to be said: truth is not
- the sort of thing that has an essence.... Those that want truth to have
- an essence want knowledge, or rationality, or inquiry, or the relation
- between thought and its object, to have an essence. Further, they want
- to be able to use their knowledge of such essences to criticize views
- they take to be false, and to point the direction of progress toward the
- discovery of more truths. James thinks these hopes are in vain. ( p.
- 162)
-
- And this version of understanding the nature of truth is at the very
- heart of the constructivist program. As we saw earlier, the
- constructivist holds that we construct knowledge. What is knowledge
- but those things that we hold to be true? Furthermore, the
- constructivist rejects the idea that there is a single foundation for
- basing the pursuit of truth on, and so the question of truth becomes
- instead an exercise in, what we see over and over again, the Rsocial
- construction of reality.S
- Are we doomed to this project of making multiple realities, of just
- telling each other stories, and letting the question of truth be settled
- by whose story is more interesting, or whose will is stronger? If we
- adhere to the Jamesean perspective, then this seems to be the case.
- But there is an alternative for inquiry - to return to PeirceUs initial
- statements and take them in a different direction.
-
- Genuinely Qualitative Research - A Vision
-
- We are at last finally free to talk about qualitative research in
- general, and thereby finally address the question outlined in the title.
- Constructivist theory has made significant inroads in the educational
- research community by offering a vision of research and theory that
- seems substantially different from the prevailing vision based on more
- traditional models of scientific inquiry. It appeals to the desire of
- many in the field to be freed from the constraints of a positivistic
- model of inquiry. (cf. Glesne & Peshkin, 1992; Lancy, 1993) It cannot
- be over-emphasized, though, that the fundamental point of
- constructivism is to deliberately refute positivistic positions. By
- taking this tack, constructivist ideas are necessarily grounded in the
- same problematic that the positivist tradition was grounded in;
- namely, a concern for establishing the proper conditions for gathering
- and using knowledge. This grounding in the pursuit of knowledge
- characterizes the basic task of modernist thinkers. But the modernist
- problematic is no longer appropriate. The predicament faced by most
- constructivists is that they sense that they need to shift beyond a
- modernist perspective, but they attempt to do so by addressing the
- matter in a modernist fashion.
- There is no escaping the fact that we are now living in a postmodern
- world. Lyotard (Lyotard, 1979; Johnson, 1992) has declared that the
- postmodern condition is based on the notion that there is no longer a
- Rgrand narrativeS that defines a single vision for culture. We have to
- abandon the search for a single perspective through which we can
- formulate a single best way of doing inquiry. Gergen (1992) shows us
- that postmodernism involves a turning away from the Enlightenment,
- with its insistence on individual cognition, rational order, and
- correspondence models of inquiry, toward a new sensibility of
- collective rationality, action, and examination of phenomena as RtextsS
- instead of repositories of fact or instantiations of theory. Thinkers
- such as Heidegger (Guignon, 1992) and Baudrillard (1988) have
- emphasized that language and its rhetorical nature play a crucial role
- in the ways that we understand our world, thereby clarifying the
- RtextnessS of the world.
- Both James and Peirce would appreciate the move in inquiry towards
- the postmodernism described above. But their characterizations of the
- situation would be quite different. James leads us away from the pole
- of strict objectivity by positing a relativist and ultimately subjective
- model of truth and therefore inquiry, while Peirce rejects the
- subjective vs objective duality altogether. It is this rejection, which
- is far more radical than any project that James or the constructivists
- would suggest,that finally allows us to build the bold and radical vision
- of qualitative research that education needs in order to function
- properly in a postmodern setting.
- As my fundamental move in this paper, I would like to show how Peirce
- gets out of the subjective-objective trap, and then show the
- consequences of this move as the basis for a genuinely qualitative
- model of educational research, one that does not slip either into the
- trap of an Ranything goesS relativistic subjectivism or the Rjust the
- factsS pseudo-scientific objectisitic positivism that has strangled the
- vitality from educational research. ( cf. Shank, 1987; Shank, 1988;
- Shank, 1990; Shank, 1992; Shank & Cunningham, 1992)
- The key to creating a pragmatically-informed model of inquiry is to
- realize that pragmatism, as Peirce conceived of it, was a totally
- radical departure from the Enlightenment scenario. That scenario
- established by the work of Descartes. In point of fact, the subjective -
- objective split that haunts modernism is a direct consequence of the
- Cartesian method of inquiry, known as the method of doubt.
- Briefly, the method consists of deliberately doubting the truth of
- anything, until we arrive at something we cannot doubt; namely, the
- famous Rcogito ergo sumS or RI think, therefore, I am.S This method
- requires both a subjective observer and the objective realm of the
- observed. This method also creates an unbridgeable split between the
- observer and the observed, keeping the observer always out of the very
- reality of that he/she is trying to observe. Peirce realized that this
- split was a function not so much of DescartesUs intended worldview,
- but of his method instead. So, in order to create a Postcartesian
- worldview, one that is free from the subjective - objective split, we
- need to create a new method.
- To make a long story short, the Pragmatic Maxim was a direct
- consequence of PeirceUs efforts to replace the Cartesian method.
- Peirce realized that DescartesUs method of doubt was flawed because
- the doubt that Descartes engendered was not genuine. Peirce chose to
- focus on genuine feelings of doubt that we feel, and the means that we
- try to alleviate them and move back into states of belief. This fixation
- of belief in the face of genuine doubt was the basis for all inquiry,
- in PeirceUs view. So long as we have no reason to doubt either our
- senses or our current understanding of things, says Peirce, then we
- have no reason not to suppose that they are true. As soon as something
- intrudes into our current state of understanding, though, we realize
- that we were not right after all, and that truth is different from what
- we had held it to be. That instance from experience, furthermore, is a
- clue that the way that we looked at reality was not quite right, and by
- that fact alone, we now have a new clue as to the ultimate nature of
- reality. Through this correctable process, held Peirce, we co-evolve,
- with the help of experience, a significant understanding of reality, one
- that we have no reason to suppose that is not true, but one that we
- cannot feel smugly is correct.
- Inquiry, then, becomes an act of RreadingS experience to gain more and
- more clues about the nature of reality. We treat the items of
- experiences as neither objective facts whose truth we can grasp in an
- unmediated way, nor as subjective opinions whose truth is simply a
- matter of what we want it to be. Rather, we treat those items as signs
- of reality. In order to read them, we have to live in the gap between
- the objective and the subjective, and we soon come to see that the gap
- as illusory.
- Our postconstructive model says that we do not construct reality,
- because reality itself is so rich and significant that all we need to do
- is to read it. And that act of reading will change both us and reality,
- since we are both co-evolving. We have the tenets of experience to
- keep us straight, and the Pragmatic Maxim to keep us from slipping into
- models of inquiry that lead us away from reality.
- What would such a model look like in practical terms? It is
- legitimately postmodern, in that it realizes that there is no one way to
- look at reality. But it rejects the notion of dependence on the observer
- and replaces it with a model of the inquirer as a participant. When we
- construe the inquirer as a participant, we see that he/she is not
- looking at reality from some outside or privileged position, but instead
- is in the middle of reality. In fact, Peirce would claim that all inquiry
- begins with us being in the middle of some already existing world, and
- that our first act is to try to make sense of that world. The
- constructivist would say that we find ourselves in a situation where
- we have to make meaning in the sense of imposing meaning on a
- situation which has no meaning until we put it there. Remember
- JamesUs old dictum of the Rbuzzing, booming confusionS we experience
- until we impose order on it? Furthermore, again following James, the
- order that we impose then becomes true so long as that truth is useful
- to us to maintain the order we have already imposed. Pretty soon, we
- find ourselves in the dilemma of being in a situation where any meaning
- is totally a product of what we have put there. What does the world
- become, then, besides ourselves? And what is instructional design
- under the aegis of this thinking but the use of oneUs intellectual will to
- impose a worldview on others, which is then claimed to be true because
- it conforms to the will of the design creator? And what does
- educational technology become, then, except for a means to enhance
- this imposition process? What about the constructivistUs claim that
- the creation of knowledge needs to shift from the designer and
- instructor to the student? What is this other than the shifting of the
- will to either the individual or the collective student? At its very
- best, constructivism with its inherent relativism and dependence of
- the subjective stance of designers and students, becomes a way to
- shift from an individual to a collective solipsism. And as Peirce
- pointed out in his famous essay on the fixation of belief, the only way
- to maintain a belief which we do not want to abandon is to hold onto it
- with tenacity and to make sure we do not find ourselves in any kind of
- circumstantial situation where that belief might get challenged. The
- path of constructivism leads inevitably to the championing of the will,
- rather than the intellect, as the supreme arbiter on what counts as
- knowledge.
- The postconstructivist alternative is to accept that we cannot impose
- our will freely on reality, but that we are not slaves to some
- configuration of reality. It accepts the fact that we are always in
- reality, and in relation to all other systems in reality. And that every
- experience has significance as a part of the whole picture of reality.
- And that reality is not constructed, or a simple set of principles
- underlying a complex surface, but is instead intelligible on its own
- terms. But we accept that the terms of intelligibility of reality are
- not directly translatable into human terms. We have to treat
- experiences as signs of the nature of reality, as answers to questions
- we are not sure how to ask. We have to shift our model of inquirer
- away from the prospector model of positivism, who seeks to find the
- nuggets of truth under the welter of experience, and the noveli
- st model of the constructivism, who seeks to create truth out of what
- seems to be available. The postconstructivist is postmodern in
- realizing that there any many paths of inquiry, but unlike the
- constructivist the postconstructivist does not hold that we impose the
- order we seek by following many paths. The model of the
- postconstructivist follows along semiotic lines, where the inquirer
- realizes that experiences are signs of order and understanding and
- meaning and that they have consequences not just in and of themselves
- but of how they are taken as signs. The model for the
- postconstructivist is that of a detective, treating experiences as clues
- and omens and symptoms of an order that represents a rich and
- complicated reality that we can only understand within a process of
- participation as part of reality itself. The postconstructivist turns
- away from knowledge per se as the starting point of inquiry, and
- acknowledges that there is just as complex and as important an inquiry
- based on increasing understanding, that an inquiry of understanding is
- just as potentially systematic as an inquiry of knowing, and that any
- real inquiry of knowing depends on an inquiry of understanding.
- So where have we ended up, on this process of going beyond
- constructivism? I want to charge that educational technology is in a
- unique position of being able to help further an inquiry into
- understanding. By developing new technologies and new tools, we can
- help students not just make meaning out of a jumble of data, but to
- look at their experiences in a participatory way and to combine and
- test patterns and clues, and to derive consequences from these clue
- patterns, and to push forward with new and unique insights. I feel that
- this was the intended mission of constructivism in the first place, but
- it cannot achieve that mission unless it gives up the notion that the
- order it seeks is simply imposed by the subjectivity of the inquirer.
- Let me conclude this entire piece and hopefully bring my points home
- in a concrete way by telling you about a computer program that John
- Ross and I designed to help illustrate a semiotically informed model of
- inquiry. We called the program ART, which is short for the Abductive
- Reasoning Tool. The idea behind ART is that there are potentially a
- myriad number of insights that can be drawn when we juxtapose two
- statements in an arbitrary fashion. We start with a topic statement,
- which the person types in. Then, the computer randomly accesses one
- of over a thousand generic wise sayings, which is physically juxtaposed
- with the initial topic and called the RreflectionS statement. The whole
- point of the process is that the inquirer feels a compulsion to link
- those two statements as a single meaningful whole, and that such a
- link will give the inquirer a new insight into the topic. We felt that the
- random linkage allowed the inquirer to explore different avenues for
- insights than he/she might ordinarily pursue. By realizing that the
- linkage is hypothetical and under no burden to be RtrueS we are allowed
- to pursue an inquiry of understanding that does not generate any new
- knowledge. We would not be able to take this stance from a
- constructivist perspective, since we would be compelled to be making
- some reality claim, or showing how the linkage we create is in some
- sense RtrueS.
- So, I turned to the program to ask: RHow can postconstructivist ideas
- help clarify the qualitative vs. quantitative debate?S
- Here is the actual reflection statement: ROur wit wraps in obscurity
- the simple natural truths in order to get credit for them.S
- I leave the task of drawing insights to you.
-
-
- References
-
- Bagley, C. & Hunter, B. (1992). Restructuring, constructivism, and
- technology: Forging a new relationship. Educational Technology, 32(7),
- 22-27.
-
- Baudrillard, J. (1988). Selected Writings. M. Poster (Ed. &
- Introduction). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
-
- Bereiter, C. (1991). Implications of connectionism for thinking about
- rules. Educational Researcher, 20(3), 10-16.
-
- Brown, J.S., Collins, A. & Duguid, P. (1989). Situated cognition and and
- the culture of learning. Educational Researcher, 18(6), 32-42.
-
- Cherryholmes, C.H. (1992). Notes on pragmatism and scientific realism.
- Educational Researcher, 21(6), 13-17.
-
- Cole, P. (1992). Constructivism revisited: A search for common ground.
- Educational Technology, 32(2), 27-34.
-
- Cunningham, D.J. (1991). Assessing constructions and conducting
- assessments: A dialogue. Educational Technology, 31(5), 13-17.
-
- Dede, C.J. (1992). The future of multimedia: Bridging to virtual worlds.
- Educational Technology, 32(5), 54-60.
-
- Duffy, T.M. & Johassen, D.H. (1991). Constructivism: New implications
- for instructional technology? Educational Technology, 31(5), 7-12.
-
- Eisner, E. (1992). Objectivity in educational research. Curriculum
- Inquiry, 22, 9-16.
-
- Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against Method. Thetford, Norfolk, UK: Verso.
-
- Gage, N.L. (1989). The paradigm wars and their aftermath: A
- RhistoricalS sketch of research on teaching since 1989. Educational
- Researcher, 18(7), 4-10.
-
- Gergen, K. (1992). Psychology in the postmodern era. The General
- Psychologist, 28(3), 10-15.
-
- Glesne, C. & Peshkin, A. (1992). Becoming Qualitative Researchers: An
- Introduction. White Plains, NY: Longman.
-
- Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of Worldmaking. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
-
- Guba, E.G. (1992). Relativism. Curriculum Inquiry, 22, 17-24.
-
- Guignon, C. (1992). Heidegger: Language as the house of being. In The
- Philosophy of Discourse: The Rhetorical Turn In Twentieth-Century
- Thought, Volume 2, C. Sills & G.H. Jensen (Eds.). Portsmouth, NH:
- Boyneton/Cook Heinemann, 163-187.
-
- House, E.R. (1991). Realism in research. Educational Researcher, 20(6),
- 2-9.
-
- House, E.R. (1992). Response to RNotes on pragmatism and scientific
- research.S Educational Researcher, 21(6), 18-19.
-
- Jacob, E. (1987). Qualitative research traditions: A review. Review of
- Educational Research, 57, 1-50.
-
- James, W. (1948). Essays in Pragmatism. NY: Hafner.
-
- Johnson, J. (1992). Lyotard: From libidinal aesthetics to language
- games. In The Philosophy Of Discourse: The Rhetorical Turn In
- Twentieth-Century Thought, Volume 2, C. Sills & G.H. Jensen (Eds.).
- Portsmouth, NH: Boyneton/Cook Heinemann, 125-154.
-
- Lakoff, G. & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors We Live By. Chicago, IL:
- University of Chicago Press.
-
- Lancy, D.F. (1993). Qualitative Research in Education: An Introduction
- to the Major Traditions. White Plains, NY: Longman.
-
- Lyotard, J-F. (1979). The Postmodern Condition. G. Bennington & B.
- Massumi (Trans.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
-
- Merrill, M.D. (1991). Constructivism and instructional design.
- Educational Technology, 31(5), 45-53.
-
- Murphy, J.P. (1990). Pragmatism: From Peirce to Davidson. Boulder,
- CO: Westview Press.
-
- Peirce, C.S. (1955). Philosophical Writings of Peirce. J. Buchler (Ed.
- and Introduction). NY: Dover.
-
- Pepper, S.C. (1942). World Hypotheses. Berkeley, CA: University of
- California Press.
-
- Perkins, D.N. (1991). Technology meets constructivism: Do they make a
- marriage? Educational Technology, 31(5), 18-23.
-
- Rizo, F.M. (1991). The controversy about quantification in social
- research: An extension of GageUs RThistoricalU sketch.S Educational
- Researcher, 20(9), 9-12.
-
- Rorty, R. (1982). Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis, MN:
- University of Minnesota Press.
-
- Salomon, G. (1991). Transcending the qualitative-quantitative debate:
- The analytic and systemic approaches to educational research.
- Educational Researcher, 20(6), 10-18.
-
- Schrag, F. (1992). In defense of positivist research paradigms.
- Educational Researcher, 21(5), 5-7.
-
- Shank, G. (1992). Educational semiotics: Threat or menace?
- Educational Psychology Review, 4, 195-210.
-
- Shank, G. (1990). Qualitative vs. quantitative research: A semiotic
- non-problem. In Semiotics: 1989, T. Prewitt, J. Deely,and K. Haworth
- (Eds.). Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 264-270.
-
- Shank, G. (1988). Three into two will go: The juxtapositional method
- of research in empirical semiotics. In Semiotics: 1987, J. Deely (Ed.).
- Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 123-127.
-
- Shank, G. (1987). Abductive strategies in educational research.
- American Journal of Semiotics, 5, 275-290.
-
- Shank, G. & Cunningham, D. (1992). The virtues of an educational
- semiotic. Midwest Educational Researcher, 5(2), 2-8.
-
- Smith, J.K. (1983). Quantitative versus qualitative research: An
- attempt to clarify the issue. Educational Researcher, 12(3), 6-13.
-
- Spiro, R.J., Feltovich, P.J., Jacobson, M.J. & Coulson, R.L. (1991).
- Cognitive flexibility, constructivism, and hypertext: Random access
- information for advanced knowledge acquisition in ill-structured
- domains. Educational Technology, 31(5), 24-33.
-
- Tolhurst, D. (1992). A checklist for evaluating content-based
- hypertext computer software. Educational Technology, 32(2), 17-21.
-
- Trimbur, J. & Holt, M. (1992). Richard Rorty: Philosophy without
- foundations. In The Philosophy Of Discourse: The Rhetorical Turn In
- Twentieth-Century Thought, Volume 1, C. Sills & G.H. Jensen (Eds.).
- Portsmouth, NH: Boyneton/Cook Heinemann, 70-94.
-