home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- Path: senator-bedfellow.mit.edu!bloom-beacon.mit.edu!news.kodak.com!news-nysernet-16.sprintlink.net!news-east1.sprintlink.net!news-peer-europe.sprintlink.net!news.sprintlink.net!netnews.com!newshub.northeast.verio.net!iad-peer.news.verio.net!iad-artgen.news.verio.net!nuq-read.news.verio.net.POSTED!not-for-mail
- Sender: Mountain Math Software <mtnmath@shell1.ncal.verio.com>
- From: paul@mtnmath.com
- Newsgroups: sci.physics,alt.sci.physics.new-theories,sci.answers,alt.answers,news.answers
- Subject: Measurement in quantum mechanics FAQ
- Message-ID: <physics-faq/measurement-in-qm-1-928331682@mtnmath.com>
- Reply-To: paul@mtnmath.com (Paul Budnik)
- Followup-To: sci.physics
- Distribution: world
- Organization: Mountain Math Software, P. O. Box 2124, Saratoga. CA 95070
- Approved: news-answers-request@MIT.EDU
- Expires: 07 Jul 99 06:54:42 PDT
- Supersedes: <physics-faq/measurement-in-qm-1-857265653@mtnmath.com>
- Keywords: FAQ quantum-mechanics measurement
- X-Posting-Frequency: posted around the 1st of each month
- X-Content-Currency: This FAQ is updated monthly.
- Summary: Describes the measurement problem in quantum mechanics and physical and metaphysical approaches to its solution.
- User-Agent: tin/pre-1.4-980117 (UNIX) (SunOS/5.6 (sun4u))
- Lines: 663
- Date: Wed, 02 Jun 1999 17:57:55 GMT
- NNTP-Posting-Host: 204.247.248.254
- X-Complaints-To: abuse@verio.net
- X-Trace: nuq-read.news.verio.net 928346275 204.247.248.254 (Wed, 02 Jun 1999 17:57:55 GMT)
- NNTP-Posting-Date: Wed, 02 Jun 1999 17:57:55 GMT
- Xref: senator-bedfellow.mit.edu sci.physics:383503 alt.sci.physics.new-theories:72082 sci.answers:10173 alt.answers:42262 news.answers:159344
-
- Posted-By: auto-faq 3.3 (Perl 5.004)
- Archive-name: physics-faq/measurement-in-qm
-
- Measurement in quantum mechanics FAQ
- Maintained by Paul Budnik, paul@mtnmath.com, http://www.mtn-
- math.com
-
-
- This FAQ describes the measurement problem in QM and approaches to its
- solution. Please help make it more complete. See ``What is needed''
- for details. Web version: http://www.mtnmath.com/faq/meas-qm.html
-
- 1. About this FAQ
-
- Last modified August 5, 1998 (section 7)
-
- The general sci.physics FAQ does a good job of dealing with technical
- questions in most areas of physics. However it has no material on
- interpretations of QM which are among the most frequently discussed
- topics in sci.physics. Hence there is a need for this supplemental
- FAQ.
-
-
- This document is probably out of date if you are reading it more than
- 30 days after the date which appears in the header.
-
-
- This FAQ is on the web at: http://www.mtnmath.com/faq/meas-qm.html
-
-
- You can get it by e-mail or FTP from rtfm.mit.edu.
-
-
- By FTP, look for the file:
-
-
- /pub/usenet/news.answers/physics-faq/measurement-in-qm
-
-
- By e-mail send a message to mail-server@rtfm.mit.edu with a blank
- subject line and the words:
-
-
- send usenet/news.answers/physics-faq/measurement-in-qm
-
-
- The main sci.physics FAQ is in this same directory with file names
- part1 through part4 and can be retrieved in the same way. You can put
- multiple send lines in a single e-mail request.
-
-
- This document, as a collection, is Copyright 1995 by Paul P. Budnik
- (paul@mtnmath.com). The individual articles are Copyright 1995 by the
- individual authors listed. All rights are reserved. Permission to
- use, copy and distribute this unmodified document by any means and for
- any purpose EXCEPT PROFIT PURPOSES is hereby granted, provided that
- both the above Copyright notice and this permission notice appear in
- all copies of the FAQ itself. Reproducing this FAQ by any means,
- included, but not limited to, printing, copying existing prints,
- publishing by electronic or other means, implies full agreement to the
- above non-profit-use clause, unless upon explicit prior written
- permission of the authors.
-
-
- This FAQ is provided by the authors ``as is''. with all its faults.
- Any express or implied warranties, including, but not limited to, any
- implied warranties of merchantability, accuracy, or fitness for any
- particular purpose, are disclaimed. If you use the information in
- this document, in any way, you do so at your own risk.
- 2. The measurement problem
-
- Paul Budnik paul@mtnmath.com
-
- The formulation of QM describes the deterministic unitary evolution of
- a wave function. This wave function is never observed experimentally.
- The wave function allows us to compute the probability that certain
- macroscopic events will be observed. There are no events and no
- mechanism for creating events in the mathematical model. It is this
- dichotomy between the wave function model and observed macroscopic
- events that is the source of the interpretation issue in QM. In
- classical physics the mathematical model talks about the things we
- observe. In QM the mathematical model by itself never produces
- observations. We must interpret the wave function in order to relate
- it to experimental observations.
-
- It is important to understand that this is not simply a philosophical
- question or a rhetorical debate. In QM one often must model systems as
- the superposition of two or more possible outcomes. Superpositions can
- produce interference effects and thus are experimentally
- distinguishable from mixed states. How does a superposition of
- different possibilities resolve itself into some particular
- observation? This question (also known as the measurement problem)
- affects how we analyze some experiments such as tests of Bell's
- inequality and may raise the question of interpretations from a
- philosophical debate to an experimentally testable question. So far
- there is no evidence that it makes any difference. The wave function
- evolves in such a way that there are no observable effects from
- macroscopic superpositions. It is only superposition of different
- possibilities at the microscopic level that leads to experimentally
- detectable interference effects.
-
- Thus it would seem that there is no criterion for objective events and
- perhaps no need for such a criterion. However there is at least one
- small fly in the ointment. In analyzing a test of Bell's inequality
- one must make some determination as to when an observation was
- complete, i. e. could not be reversed. These experiments depend on the
- timing of macroscopic events. The natural assumption is to use
- classical thermodynamics to compute the probability that a macroscopic
- event can be reversed. This however implies that there is some
- objective process that produces the particular observation. Since no
- such objective process exists in current models this suggests that QM
- is an incomplete theory. This might be thought of as the Einstein
- interpretation of QM, i. e., that there are objective physical
- processes that create observations and we do not yet understand these
- processes. This is the view of the compiler of this document.
-
- For more information:
-
- Ed. J. Wheeler, W. Zurek, Quantum theory and measurement, Princeton
- University Press, 1983.
-
- J. S. Bell, Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics, Cambridge
- University Press, 1987.
-
- R.I.G. Hughes, The Structure and Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics,
- Harvard University Press, 1989.
-
- 3. Schrodinger's cat
-
- Paul Budnik paul@mtnmath.com
-
-
- In 1935 Schrodinger published an essay describing the conceptual
- problems in QM[1]. A brief paragraph in this essay described the cat
- paradox.
- One can even set up quite ridiculous cases. A cat is penned up
- in a steel chamber, along with the following diabolical device
- (which must be secured against direct interference by the cat):
- in a Geiger counter there is a tiny bit of radioactive
- substance, so small that perhaps in the course of one hour one
- of the atoms decays, but also, with equal probability, perhaps
- none; if it happens, the counter tube discharges and through a
- relay releases a hammer which shatters a small flask of
- hydrocyanic acid. If one has left this entire system to itself
- for an hour, one would say that the cat still lives if meanwhile
- no atom has decayed. The first atomic decay would have poisoned
- it. The Psi function for the entire system would express this by
- having in it the living and the dead cat (pardon the expression)
- mixed or smeared out in equal parts.
-
-
- It is typical of these cases that an indeterminacy originally
- restricted to the atomic domain becomes transformed into
- macroscopic indeterminacy, which can then be resolved by direct
- observation. That prevents us from so naively accepting as valid
- a ``blurred model'' for representing reality. In itself it would
- not embody anything unclear or contradictory. There is a
- difference between a shaky or out-of-focus photograph and a
- snapshot of clouds and fog banks.
-
- We know that superposition of possible outcomes must exist
- simultaneously at a microscopic level because we can observe
- interference effects from these. We know (at least most of us know)
- that the cat in the box is dead, alive or dying and not in a smeared
- out state between the alternatives. When and how does the model of
- many microscopic possibilities resolve itself into a particular
- macroscopic state? When and how does the fog bank of microscopic
- possibilities transform itself to the blurred picture we have of a
- definite macroscopic state. That is the measurement problem and
- Schrodinger's cat is a simple and elegant explanations of that
- problem.
-
- References:
-
- [1] E. Schrodinger, ``Die gegenwartige Situation in der
- Quantenmechanik,'' Naturwissenschaftern. 23 : pp. 807-812; 823-823,
- 844-849. (1935). English translation: John D. Trimmer, Proceedings of
- the American Philosophical Society, 124, 323-38 (1980), Reprinted in
- Quantum Theory and Measurement, p 152 (1983).
-
-
-
- 4. The Copenhagen interpretation
-
- Paul Budnik paul@mtnmath.com
-
- This is the oldest of the interpretations. It is based on Bohr's
- notion of `complementarity'. Bohr felt that the classical and quantum
- mechanical models were two complementary ways of dealing with physics
- both of which were necessary. Bohr felt that an experimental
- observation collapsed or ruptured (his term) the wave function to make
- its future evolution consistent with what we observe experimentally.
- Bohr understood that there was no precise way to define the exact
- point at which collapse occurred. Any attempt to do so would yield a
- different theory rather than an interpretation of the existing theory.
- Nonetheless he felt it was connected to conscious observation as this
- was the ultimate criterion by which we know a specific observation has
- occurred.
-
- References:
-
- N. Bohr, The quantum postulate and recent the recent development of
- atomic theory, Nature, 121, 580-89 (1928), Reprinted in Quantum Theory
- and Measurement, p 87, (1983).
-
-
-
- 5. Is QM a complete theory?
-
- Paul Budnik paul@mtnmath.com
-
- Einstein did not believe that God plays dice and thought a more
- complete theory would predict the actual outcome of experiments. He
- argued[1] that quantities that are conserved absolutely (such as
- momentum or energy) must correspond to some objective element of
- physical reality. Because QM does not model this he felt it must be
- incomplete.
-
- It is possible that events are the result of objective physical
- processes that we do not yet understand. These processes may determine
- the actual outcome of experiments and not just their probabilities.
- Certainly that is the natural assumption to make. Any one who does not
- understand QM and many who have only a superficial understanding
- naturally think that observations come about from some objective
- physical process even if they think we can only predict probabilities.
-
- There have been numerous attempts to develop such alternatives. These
- are often referred to as `hidden variables' theories. Bell proved that
- such theories cannot deal with quantum entanglement without
- introducing explicitly nonlocal mechanisms[2]. Quantum entanglement
- refers to the way observations of two particles are correlated after
- the particles interact. It comes about because the conservation laws
- are exact but most observations are probabilistic. Nonlocal
- operations in hidden variables theories might not seem such a drawback
- since QM itself must use explicit nonlocal mechanism to deal with
- entanglement. However in QM the non-locality is in a wave function
- which most do not consider to be a physical entity. This makes the
- non-locality less offensive or at least easier to rationalize away.
-
- It might seem that the tables have been turned on Einstein. The very
- argument he used in EPR to show QM must be incomplete requires that
- hidden variables models have explicit nonlocal operations. However it
- is experiments and not theoretical arguments that now must decide the
- issue. Although all experiments to date have produced results
- consistent with the predictions of QM, there is general agreement that
- the existing experiments are inconclusive[3]. There is no conclusive
- experimental confirmation of the nonlocal predictions of QM. If these
- experiments eventually confirm locality and not QM Einstein will be
- largely vindicated for exactly the reasons he gave in EPR. Final
- vindication will depend on the development of a more complete theory.
-
- Most physicists (including Bell before his untimely death) believe QM
- is correct in predicting locality is violated. Why do they have so
- much more faith in the strange formalism of QM than in basic
- principles like locality or the notion that observations are produced
- by objective processes? I think the reason may be that they are
- viewing these problems in the wrong conceptual framework. The term
- `hidden variables' suggests a theory of classical-like particles with
- additional hidden variables. However quantum entanglement and the
- behavior of multi-particle systems strongly suggests that whatever
- underlies quantum effects it is nothing like classical particles. If
- that is so then any attempt to develop a more complete theory in this
- framework can only lead to frustration and failure. The fault may not
- be in classical principles like locality or determinism. They failure
- may only be in the imagination of those who are convinced that no more
- complete theory is possible.
-
- One alternative to classical particles is to think of observations as
- focal points in state space of nonlinear transformations of the wave
- function. Attractors in Chaos theory provide one model of processes
- like this. Perhaps there is an objective physical wave function and QM
- only models the average or statistical behavior of this wave function.
- Perhaps the structure of this physical wave function determines the
- probability that the wave function will transform nonlinearly at a
- particular location. If this is so then probability in QM combines two
- very different kinds of probabilities. The first is the probability
- associated with our state of ignorance about the detailed behavior of
- the physical wave function. The second is the probability that the
- physical wave function will transform with a particular focal point.
-
- A model of this type might be able to explain existing experimental
- results and still never violate locality. I have advocated a class of
- models of this type based on using a discretized finite difference
- equation rather then a continuous differential equation to model the
- wave function[4]. The nonlinearity that must be introduced to
- discretize the difference equation is a source of chaotic like
- behavior. In this model the enforcement of the conservation laws
- comes about through a process of converging to a stable state.
- Information that enforces these laws is stored holographic-like over a
- wide region.
-
- Most would agree that the best solution to the measurement problem
- would be a more complete theory. Where people part company is in their
- belief in whether such a thing is possible. All attempts to prove it
- impossible (starting with von Neumann[5]) have been shown to be
- flawed[6]. It is in part Bell's analysis of these proofs that led to
- his proof about locality in QM. Bell has transformed a significant
- part of this issue to one experimenters can address. If nature
- violates locality in the way QM predicts then a local deterministic
- theory of the kind Einstein was searching for is not possible. If QM
- is incorrect in making these predictions then a more accurate and more
- complete theory is a necessity. Such a theory is quite likely to
- account for events by an objective physical process.
-
- References: [1] A. Einstein, B. Podolsky and N. Rosen, Can quantum-
- mechanical descriptions of physical reality be considered complete?,
- Physical Review, 47, 777 (1935). Reprinted in Quantum Theory and
- Measurement, p. 139, (1987).
-
- [2] J. S. Bell, On the Einstein Podolosky Rosen Paradox, Physics, 1,
- 195-200 (1964). Reprinted in Quantum Theory and Measurement, p. 403,
- (1987).
-
- [3] P. G. Kwiat, P. H. Eberhard, A. M. Steinberg, and R. Y. Chiao,
- Proposal for a loophole-free Bell inequality experiment, Physical
- Reviews A, 49, 3209 (1994).
-
- [4] P. Budnik, Developing a local deterministic theory to account for
- quantum mechanical effects, hep-th/9410153, (1995).
-
- [5] J. von Neumann, The Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics,
- Princeton University Press, N. J., (1955).
-
- [6] J. S. Bell, On the the problem of hidden variables in quantum
- mechanics, Reviews of Modern Physics, 38, 447-452, (1966). Reprinted
- in Quantum Theory and Measurement, p. 397, (1987).
-
- 6. The shut up and calculate interpretation
-
- Paul Budnik paul@mtnmath.com
-
- This is the most popular of interpretations. It recognizes that the
- important content of QM is the mathematical models and the ability to
- apply those models to real experiments. As long as we understand the
- models and their application we do not need an interpretation.
-
- Advocates of this position like to argue that the existing framework
- allows us to solve all real problems and that is all that is
- important. Franson's analysis of Aspect's experiment[1] shows this
- is not entirely true. Because there is no objective criterion in QM
- for determining when a measurement is complete (and hence
- irreversible) there is no objective criterion for measuring the delays
- in a test of Bell's inequality. If the demise of Schrodinger's cat
- may not be determined until someone looks in the box (see item 2) how
- are we to know when a measurement in tests of Bells inequality is
- irreversible and thus measure the critical timing in these
- experiments?
-
- References:
-
- [1] J. D. Franson, Bell's Theorem and delayed determinism, Physical
- Review D, 31, 2529-2532, (1985).
-
-
- 7. Bohm's theory
-
- Paul Budnik paul@mtnmath.com
-
- Bohm's interpretation is an explicitly nonlocal mechanistic model.
- Just as Bohr saw the philosophical principle of complementarity as
- having broader implications than quantum mechanics Bohm saw a deep
- relationship between locality violation and the wholeness or unity of
- all that exists. Bohm was perhaps the first to truly understand the
- nonlocal nature of quantum mechanics. Bell acknowledged the importance
- of Bohm's work in helping develop Bell's ideas about locality in QM.
-
- References: D. Bohm, A suggested interpretation of quantum theory in
- terms of "hidden" variables I and II, Physical Review,85, 155-93
- (1952). Reprinted in Quantum Theory and Measurement, p. 369, (1987).
-
- D. Bohm & B.J. Hiley, The Undivided Universe: an ontological
- interpretation of quantum theory (Routledge: London & New York, 1993).
-
- Recently there has been renewed interest in Bohmian mechanics. D.
- D"urr, S. Goldstein, N Zanghi, Phys. Lett. A 172, 6 (1992) K. Berndl
- et al., Il Nuovo Cimento Vol. 110 B, N. 5-6 (1995).
-
- Peter Holland's book The Quantum Theory of Motion (Cambridge
- University Press 1993) contains many pictures of numerical simulations
- of Bohmian trajectories.
-
- There was a recent two part article in Physics Today based in part on
- Bohm's approach. The author, Sheldon Goldstein, has published a number
- of other papers on this and related subjects many of which are
- available at his web site, http://math.rutgers.edu/~oldstein. S
- Goldstein, Quantum Theory Without Observers, Physics Today Part 1:
- March 1998, 42-46, Part 2: April 1998 38-42.
-
- 8. Lawrence R. Meadrmead@ocra.st.usm.ed The Transactional Interpreta-
- tion of Quantum Mechanics
-
- The transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics (J.G. Cramer,
- Phys. Rev. D 22, 362 (1980) ) has received little attention over the
- one and one half decades since its conception. It is to be emphasized
- that, like the Many-Worlds and other interpretations, the
- transactional interpretation (TI) makes no new physical predictions;
- it merely reinterprets the physical content of the very same
- mathematical formalism as used in the ``standard'' textbooks, or by
- all other interpretations.
- The following summarizes the TI. Consider a two-body system (there are
- no additional complications arising in the many-body case); the
- quantum mechanical object located at space-time point (R_1,T_1) and
- another with which it will interact at (R_2,T_2). A quantum mechanical
- process governed by E=h\nu, conservation laws, etc., occurs between
- the two in the following way.
-
- 1) The ``emitter'' (E) at (R_1,T_1) emits a retarded ``offer wave''
- (OW) \\Psi. This wave (or state vector) is an actual physical wave
- and not (as in the Copenhagen interpretation) just a ``probability''
- wave.
-
- 2) The ``absorber'' (A) at (R_2,T_2) receives the OW and is stimulated
- to emit an advanced ``echo'' or ``confirmation wave'' (CW)
- proportional to \\Psi at R_2 backward in time; the proportionality
- factor is \\Psi* (R_2,T_2).
-
- 3) The advanced wave which arrives at 'E' is \\Psi \\Psi* and is
- presumed to be the probability, P, that the transaction is complete
- (ie., that an interaction has taken place).
-
- 4) The exchange of OW's and CW's continues until a net exchange of
- energy and other conserved quantities occurs dictated by the quantum
- boundary conditions of the system, at which point the ``transaction''
- is complete. In effect, a standing wave in space-time is set up
- between 'E' and 'A', consistent with conservation of energy and
- momentum (and angular momentum). The formation of this superposition
- of advanced and retarded waves is the equivalent to the Copenhagen
- ``collapse of the state vector''. An observer perceives only the
- completed transaction, however, which he would interpret as a single,
- retarded wave (photon, for example) traveling from 'E' to 'A'.
-
- Q1. When does the ``collapse'' occur?
-
- A1. This is no longer a meaningful question. The quantum measurement
- process happens ``when'' the transaction (OW sent - CW received -
- standing wave formed with probability \\Psi \\Psi*) is finished - and
- this happens over a space-time interval; thus, one cannot point to a
- time of collapse, only to an interval of collapse (consistent with
- relativity).
-
- Q2. Wait a moment. What you are describing is time reversal invariant.
- But for a massive particle you have to use the Schrodinger equation
- and if \\Psi is a solution (OW), then \\Psi* is not a solution. What
- gives?
-
- A2. Remember that the CW must be time-reversed, and in general must be
- relativistically invariant; ie., a solution of the Dirac equation.
- Now (eg., see Bjorken and Drell, Relativistic QM), the nonrelativistic
- limit of that is not just the Schrodinger equation, but two
- Schrodinger equations: the time forward equation satisfied by \\Psi,
- and the time reversed Schrodinger equation (which has i --> -i) for
- which \\Psi* is the correct solution. Thus, \\Psi* is the correct CW
- for \\Psi as the OW.
-
- Q3. What about other objects in other places?
-
- A3. The whole process is three dimensional (space). The retarded OW is
- sent in all spatial directions. Other objects receiving the OW are
- sending back their own CW advanced waves to 'E' also. Suppose the
- receivers are labeled 1 and 2, with corresponding energy changes E_1
- and E_2. Then the state vector of the system could be written as a
- superposition of waves in the standard fashion. In particular, two
- possible transactions could form: exchange of energy E_1 with
- probability P_1=\\Psi_1 \\Psi_1*, or E_2 with probability P_2=\\Psi_2
- \\Psi_2*. Here, the conjugated waves are the advanced waves evaluated
- at the position of R_1 or R_2 respectively according to rule 3 above.
-
- Q4. Involving as it does an entire space-time interval, isn't this a
- nonlocal ``theory''?
-
- A4. Yes, indeed; it was explicitly designed that way. As you know from
- Bell's theorem, no ``theory'' can agree with quantum mechanics unless
- it is nonlocal in character. In effect, the TI is a hidden variables
- theory as it postulates a real waves traveling in space-time.
-
- Q5. What happens to OW's that are not ``absorbed'' ?
-
- A5. Inasmuch as they do not stimulate a responsive CW, they just
- continue to travel onward until they do. This does not present any
- problems since in that case no energy or momentum or any other
- physical observable is transferred.
-
- Q6. How about all of the standard measurement thought experiments like
- the EPR, Schrodinger's cat, Wigner's friend, and Renninger's negative-
- result experiment?
-
- A6. The interpretational difficulties with the latter three are due to
- the necessity of deciding when the Copenhagen state reduction occurs.
- As we saw above, in the TI there is no specific time when the
- transaction is complete. The EPR is a completeness argument requiring
- objective reality. The TI supplies this as well; the OW and CW are
- real waves, not waves of probability.
-
- Q7. I am curious about more technical details. Can you give a further
- reference?
-
- A7. If you understand the theory of ``advanced'' and ``retarded''
- waves (out of electromagnetism and optics), many of the details of TI
- calculations can be found in: Reviews of Modern Physics, Vol. 58, July
- 1986, pp. 647-687 available on the WWW as:
- http://mist.npl.washington.edu/npl/int_rep/tiqm/TI_toc.html
-
- 9. Complex probabilities
-
- References; Saul Youssef Quantum Mechanics as Complex Probability
- Theory, hep-th 9307019. S. Youssef, Mod.Phys.Lett.A 28(1994)2571.
-
- 10. Quantum logic
-
- References: R.I.G. Hughes, The Structure and Interpretation of Quantum
- Mechanics, pp. 178-217, Harvard University Press, 1989.
-
- 11. Consistent histories
-
- References: R. B. Griffiths, Consistent Histories and the
- Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Journal of statistical Physics.,
- 36(12):219-272(1984)
-
- M. Gell-Mann and J. B. Hartle, in Complexity, Entropy and the Physics
- of Information, edited by W. Zurek, Santa Fe Institute Studies in the
- Sciences of Complexity Vol. VIII, Addison-Wesley, Reading, 1990. Also
- in Proceedings of the $3$rd International Symposion on the Foundations
- of Quantum Mechanics in the Light of New Technology, edited by S.
- Kobayashi, H. Ezawa, Y. Murayama and S. Nomura, Physical Society of
- Japan, Tokyo, 1990
-
- R. B. Griffiths, Phys. Rev. Lett. 70, 2201 (1993)
-
- R. Omn\`es, Rev. Mod. Phys. 64, 339 (1992)
-
-
- In this approach serious problems arise. This is best pointed out in:
- B. d'Espagnat, J. Stat. Phys. 56, 747 (1989)
-
- F. Dowker und A. Kent, On the Consistent Histories Approach to Quantum
- Mechanics, University of Cambridge Preprint DAMTP/94-48, Isaac Newton
- Institute for Mathematical Sciences Preprint NI 94006, August 1994.
-
-
- 12. Spontaneous reduction models
-
- Reference:
-
- G. C. Ghirardi, A. Rimini and T. Weber, Phys. Rev. D 34, 470 (1986).
-
- 13. What is needed?
-
- All comments suggested and contributions are welcome. We currently
- have nothing but references on Complex Probabilities, Quantum Logic,
- Consistent Histories and Spontaneous Reduction Models. The entries on
- the following topics are minimal and should be replaced by complete
- articles.
-
-
- + Copenhagen interpretation
-
- + Relative State (Everett)
-
- + Shut up and calculate
-
- + Bohm's theory
-
- Alternative views on any of the topics and suggestions for additional
- topics are welcome.
-
- 14. Is this a real FAQ?
-
- Paul Budnik paul@mtnmath.com
-
- A FAQ is generally understood to be a reasonably objective set of
- answers to frequently asked questions in a news group. In cases where
- an issue is controversial the FAQ should include all credible opinions
- and/or the consensus view of the news group.
-
- Establishing factual accuracy is not easy. No consensus is possible on
- interpretations of QM because many aspects of interpretations involve
- metaphysical questions. My intention is that this be an objective
- accurate FAQ that allows for the expression of all credible relevant
- opinions. I did not call it a FAQ until I had significant feedback
- from the `sci.physics' group. I have responded to all criticism and
- have made some corrections. Nonetheless there have been a couple of
- complaints about this not being a real FAQ and there is one issue that
- has not been resolved.
-
- If anyone thinks there are technical errors in the FAQ please say what
- you think the errors are. I will either fix the problem or try to
- reach on a consensus with the help of the `sci.physics' group about
- what is factually accurate. I do not feel this FAQ should be limited
- to noncontroversial issues. A FAQ on measurement in quantum mechanics
- should highlight and underscore the conceptual issues and problems in
- the theory.
-
- The one area that has been discussed and not resolved is the status of
- locality in Everett's interpretation. Here is what I believe the facts
- are.
-
-
- Eberhard proved that any theory that reproduces the predictions of QM
- is nonlocal[1]. This proof assumes contrafactual definiteness (CFD) or
- that one could have done a different experiment and have gotten a
- definite result. This assumption is widely used in statistical
- arguments. Here is what Eberhard means by nonlocal:
-
-
- Let us consider two measuring apparata located in two different
- places A and B. There is a knob a on apparatus A and a knob b on
- apparatus B. Since A and B are separated in space, it is
- natural to think what will happen at A is independent of the
- setting of knob b and vice versa. The principles of relativity
- seem to impose this point of view if the time at which the knobs
- are set and the time of the measurements are so close that, in
- the time laps, no light signal can travel from A to B and vice
- versa. Then, no signal can inform a measurement apparatus of
- what the knob setting on the other is. However, there are cases
- in which the predictions of quantum theory make that
- independence assumption impossible. If quantum theory is true,
- there are cases in which the results of the measurements A will
- depend on the setting of the knob b and/or the results of the
- measurements in B will depend on the setting of the knob a.[1]
-
- It is logically possible to deny CFD and thus to avoid Eberhard's
- proof. This assumption can be made in Everett's interpretation.
- Everett's interpretation does not imply CFD is false and CFD can be
- assumed false in other interpretations. I do not think it is
- reasonable to deny CFD in some experiments and not others but that is
- a judgment call on which intelligent people can differ.
-
- It is mathematically impossible to have a unitary relativistic wave
- function from which one can compute probabilities that will violate
- Bell's inequality. A unitary wave function does satisfy CFD and thus
- is subject to Eberhard's proof. This is a problem for some advocates
- of Everett who insist that only the wave function exists. There is no
- wave function consistent with both quantum mechanics and relativity
- and it is mathematically impossible to construct such a function.
- Quantum field theory requires a nonlocal and thus nonrelativistic
- state model. The predications of quantum field theory are the same in
- any frame of reference but the mechanisms that generate nonlocal
- effects must operate in an absolute frame of reference. Quantum
- uncertainty makes this seemingly paradoxical situation possible. There
- is a nonlocal effect but we cannot tell if the effect went from A to B
- or B to A because of quantum uncertainty. As a result the predictions
- are the same in any frame of reference but any mechanism that produces
- these predictions must be tied to an absolute frame of reference.
-
- There is a certain Alice in Wonderland quality to arguments on these
- issues. Many physicists claim that classical mathematics does not
- apply to some aspects of quantum mechanics, yet there is no other
- mathematics. The wave function model is a classical causal
- deterministic model. The computation of probabilities from that model
- is as well. The aspect of quantum mechanics that one can claim lies
- outside of classical mathematics is the interpretation of those
- probabilities. Most physicists believe these probabilities are
- irreducible, i. e., do not come from a more fundamental deterministic
- process the way probabilities do in classical physics. Because there
- is no mathematical theory of irreducible probabilities one can invent
- new metaphysics to interpret these probabilities and here is where the
- problems and confusion rest. Some physicists claim there is new
- metaphysics and within this metaphysics quantum mechanics is local.
-
- References:
-
- P. H. Eberhard, Bell's Theorem without Hidden Variables, Il Nuovo
- Cimento, V38 B 1, p 75, Mar 1977.
-