$Unique_ID{bob00092} $Pretitle{} $Title{Richard Strauss Chapter III: Later Instrumental Works - Part I} $Subtitle{} $Author{Newman, Ernest} $Affiliation{} $Subject{music form musical poetic first strauss work ideas programme movement} $Date{1908} $Log{} Title: Richard Strauss Author: Newman, Ernest Date: 1908 Chapter III: Later Instrumental Works - Part I Aus Italien (1886), in which Strauss made his first cautious step away from the older abstract to the more modern poetic forms, was, according to tradition, largely influenced by the teaching of Alexander Ritter. But we need not attribute too much to this influence; no doubt much of its strength came from the fact that it operated upon Strauss just when his musical imagination was losing some of its first metallic hardness and softening into something more purely emotional. We have already noted signs of this here and there in the later work of his first period, notably in the Piano Quartet. There seems, in fact, to have been a psychological change going on within him at this time, which probably had its origin in some subtle physiological change - some inteneration of the mental and bodily tissues that brought with it a more nervous susceptibility to feeling. The journey to Italy in the spring of 1886 no doubt accelerated this process; Italy disturbed and inspired the young man's imagination as it has always done that of sensitive Northerners - Goethe, Tchaikovski, and Hugo Wolf, for example - when they have visited it for the first time. In Aus Italien, which was written immediately after his return from the south, the pulse of Strauss's music is perceptibly quickened and the temperature of it heightened by the physical and mental sensations he had experienced in Italy ^* - more potent influences in his development, we may be sure, than all the arguments of Ritter. The emotional glow in the first and third movements is as far above anything we meet with even in the andante of the Piano Quartet as the warmth of that is above the average temperature of the preceding works. A casual survey of the first movement alone will show that here everything is generated and controlled by emotion. There is no music-making for music-making's sake, no mere strenuous turning of the wheel regardless of whether there is any corn being ground or not, as there was in much of the earlier vigorous but steely work; here the whole movement has its genesis in a personal emotion that has been sincerely felt and lived through. The music, too, has the broad deliberate onward sweep from its beginning to its end that is characteristic of so many of the later symphonic poems of Strauss; and although the composer here has wisely let the ideas determine the form, instead of attempting to fit them into a preconceived frame, the development is perfectly logical and the movement as a whole finely balanced and organic. In the third movement, again, depicting the feelings of the composer "By Sorrento's Strand," there is a sensitiveness to pure beauty - to the quality in music that gives the ear the same deep contented joy that the form and colour of beautiful flowers give to the eye - that marks a great advance upon anything of the kind that Strauss had attempted previously. Both this and the first movement, indeed, remain to this day among his most truly felt and exquisitely expressed works. We notice, again, in this third movement, the beginning of Strauss's many efforts at literary and pictorial characterization in music - though as yet the tendency is kept within legitimate bounds. The second movement is both thematically and emotionally interesting and is well worked out. The finale, a representation of Neapolitan popular life, ^* is the least satisfactory movement of the work. There is a breezy vitality in a good deal of it, but as a whole it does not hang together, the music often bustling along in a way that is meant to be vivacious but is merely fussy. [Footnote *: Strauss is still peculiarly susceptible to sunlight. He has told more than one friend that he cannot compose in the winter; light and warmth are necessary before his ideas will begin to flow.] [Footnote *: The first subject of the finale is the melody of Denza's song "Funiculi, funicula," which Strauss had heard in Naples. He thought it was a Neapolitan folksong and has so designated it in his score] How much of the new warmth of feeling and the more vitalized workmanship that marked Aus Italien out from the earlier music of Strauss was the outcome of his having a poetic scheme to follow may be guessed from the Violin Sonata composed in the following year. Here, although at times the greater depth of emotion and the superior technique that Strauss had now acquired are clearly evident, he is obviously not completely at his ease in the more abstract sonata form. The first movement is indeed remarkably rich, strong, and well constructed; the themes are both striking in themselves and are treated with much fertility of device, and the music flows on in an almost unbroken current from the first bar to the last. But the andante, though there is a certain artificial charm in some of the writing, notably in the arabesques of the latter portion, has nothing like the depth of meaning of either of the slow sections of Aus Italien. To use a Coleridgian distinction, it comes from the fancy rather than from the imagination; it is graceful and pleasant, but the feeling is slightly self-conscious and rises from no great depth. The finale is almost wholly in Strauss's earlier manner - is, indeed, rather more scrambling and inorganic than most of his youthful finales. The Sonata marks Strauss's final breach with the abstract classical form; he now recognized that what he had to say was ill-fitted for this form, and that it could only come to full expression in the freer forms of poetic music. This is not the place to attempt either a summary of the history of programme music or a detailed analysis of the aesthetic problems it involves. ^* A brief survey of the question is, however, necessary if we desire to apply a critical criterion to the later works of Strauss or to understand their significance in the history of modern music. [Footnote *: The student who is interested in the subject will find a mass of historical information in Professor Niecks's recent large book, "Programme Music." For an attempt to solve the general aesthetic question perhaps I may be allowed to refer to a lengthy essay of my own in my "Musical Studies" (1905).] Roughly speaking, there are two kinds of musical idea; the one is self-existent and self-sufficient, referring to nothing external to itself, and requiring no knowledge of anything but itself for the full understanding of it; the other is prompted by some previous literary or pictorial concept and can only be fully understood in conjunction with this. At the one extreme stand musical ideas like those of the average fugue, or the "subjects" of a Mozart symphony; at the other extreme stand ideas like those of a song or an opera. Midway between these two there lies a peculiar kind of musical idea that is not actually associated with words - as in the opera or the song - but which, though it exists only in a purely instrumental form, really owes its being to the desire to represent in music some other idea non-musical in its origin. Types of this kind of musical idea are seen in the tumultuous string passages near the end of the "Leonora No. 3" overture, which symbolize the over-whelming joy of Leonora and Florestan at the happy ending to their sufferings; in the anguish-stricken opening phrases of Gluck's "Iphigenia in Aulis" overture, which express the grief of Agamemnon; in the two melodies - one stern and forceful, the other gentle and suppliant - that denote respectively Coriolanus and the women in Beethoven's "Coriolanus" overture; in the delicate flitting phrases that depict the fairies or the braying phrase that depicts the ass in Mendelssohn's "Midsummer Night's Dream" overture; in the thoughtful, mournful theme which, in Wagner's "Faust" overture, portrays the old weary philosopher of Goethe's poem; in the phrases that suggest the flowing water in the introduction to "The Rhine-gold"; in the phrases that suggest the whirring of the spinning-wheels in "The Flying Dutchman"; in the rhythms that suggest the galloping horse in Liszt's "Mazeppa"; in the softly swaying harmonies that depict the rustling leaves in the "Waldweben" in "Siegfried"; in the undulating melodies in which Bach often tries to suggest a river, or the broken phrases in which he tries to convey the idea of a man stumbling. We may conveniently call the first kind of music abstract and the second poetic, though we must always remember that a great deal of music that is ostensibly abstract is really poetic in its origin. There are many apparently abstract compositions which, like the "Revolutionary" Etude of Chopin, we know to have originated in a definite external stimulus; and there must be a great many others which, though the composer has left us wholly without clue to their poetic intention, are certainly translations into tone of the impressions made by some book, or picture, or event, or aspect of nature. Probably, if the truth were known, two-thirds of the music of the past two hundred years belong rather to the category of poetic than to that of abstract music. So far, however, we have been considering only the basic ideas of a piece of music. These do not in themselves, of course, constitute a musical composition, but only the material out of which it is to be made; and it is in this process of building fragments of musical material into a large and organic whole that the great point of contention arises between the abstract and the poetic musicians. We are face to face, in fact, with the great and eternal problem of form - the problem of making each bar of a composition lead so naturally and logically into the next that the whole tissue seems like a living organism, and of so balancing one part with another, and making each detail a necessary factor in the total effect, that the composition as a whole satisfies our sense of design as a perfect piece of architecture does. Composers have always instinctively striven after this architectural balance and proportion; even the simplest song or dance shows it in its modulation, half-way through, into the key of the dominant and its return to the key of the tonic. In the development of modern musical form it was inevitable that for some time the composers should concentrate most of their attention on what we may call the more external aspect of "design" in music - on securing an obvious and rather artificial balance, proportion, and orderliness. We see the effect of this in the conventional key-schemes and the sharply separated "subjects" of the average eighteenth-century symphony or sonata. Men were voyaging on new seas and felt it unsafe to venture out of sight of land; they invented subjects so pointedly different in style that no one could help perceiving where one ended and the other began; and their simple schemes of key-contrast and key-sequence threw no strain on a sense of tonality that was as yet almost in its infancy. The obvious lacunae in the symphonic structure of Mozart and Haydn were filled up by Beethoven. He made each part of the music grow organically out of and into the parts that followed and preceded it; he introduced a wealth of new detail - melodic, harmonic, rhythmic, and modulatory - yet built it all so firmly and logically together that the total effect is as of some great building of the utmost harmony of design, in which practically every stone that is used plays an indispensable part. In every sphere of music the same ideal of form has to be striven after - logical continuity of tissue and perfect balance between the details and the mass. But it is evident that abstract music can as a rule attain this ideal much more easily than poetic music. Music that is concerned with nothing but self-existent themes and their possibilities of metamorphosis has necessarily fewer difficulties in its way than poetic music, which has to pursue simultaneously two lines of development; for it has to weave a connected musical tissue by the same process of evolution of new matter from old that goes on in abstract music, and at the same time it has to follow the lines laid down for it by its poetic basis. It is in the attempt to serve these two masters at once that so much poetic music comes to grief; if the music pursues merely its own line of development it is apt to obscure or misinterpret the programme; ^* while if the programme is followed with too canine a fidelity the total design of the work is likely to be imperfect - for literary form is not musical form. The early nineteenth-century experimenters in poetic music were soon made to realize their dilemma. Berlioz never succeeded in discovering the new form that would fit his new ideas. Liszt came nearer to the ideal in his symphonic poems, in which the poetic scheme was made to unfold within the frame of a single movement, instead of the three or four or five movements of the classical symphony and the programme symphony of Berlioz. But Liszt's powers of construction were not equal to his powers of invention. He could illustrate the details of a poetic subject expressively enough; but almost all his symphonic poems are weak in musical architecture. He never succeeded in striking the proper balance between the claims of the poetic scheme and the claims of the musical tissue to develop in its own way; and in his anxiety that nothing of his programme shall remain unrevealed he often writes music that is a mere disorganized drifting from one literary point to another. He is a musical illustrator rather than a musical builder. [Footnote *: I here use the term "programme" to cover every kind and every form of subject that music may attempt to express. In this sense the poem of a song or an opera is its "programme." Every student knows that there can be the same clashing between the words and the music of a song, for example, as between the programme and the music of a symphonic poem. On the one hand Liszt, in his symphonic poems, often pursues the literary idea at the expense of the purely musical development; on the other hand Schubert often writes pure music that does violent injustice to the poem it is supposed to illustrate.] Poetic music, then, was for a long time in a dilemma. The method of Liszt and his more adventurous followers produced symphonic poems that were often admirably veracious in detail, but ill-knit and incoherent as a whole; the timid neo-classicists, on the other hand, merely gave literary titles to pieces written in the conventional symphonic form. Yet the way out of the difficulty was perfectly plain. Since poetic music has to tell a story and at the same time to talk sound musical sense - for the ear will not tolerate, in the name of literature, what it feels to be musical nonsense - obviously the proper course is to choose a programme the development of which will assist the purely musical evolution instead of placing obstacles in the way of it. The musical tissue must always be the paramount consideration. The poetic scheme to be illustrated should therefore, in the first place, be as concise and uncomplicated as possible, for, as music requires a large space for its own peculiar kind of development, no more than a hint from poetry is needed to start a lengthy musical discourse. Secondly, since much of what we call "development" in music consists of the re-presentation of the same thematic material in different forms - the ear finding one of its greatest pleasures in the recognition of variety in unity and unity in variety - it follows that the later episodes in the poetic scheme should bear such a relation to the earlier ones as can be logically expressed by metamorphoses of the earlier musical themes. The prelude to "Lohengrin" is so perfect because its underlying poetic idea - the angel hosts emerging from the distance, bearing the Grail nearer and nearer the spectator until its radiance blinds him, and then slowly receding into the distance again - is one that lends itself admirably to a typical musical device - that of starting a theme in the simplest terms, working up the possibilities latent in it to a huge climax, and then refining it away again to vanishing point. Here, of course, there is practically no incident; and it is when the composer of poetic music comes to work upon a scheme that involves much incident that he realizes the difficulty of making his poetic and his musical development run on the same lines. It is this difficulty that Strauss has come nearer solving than any other composer of symphonic poems, partly because he has mostly been judicious in the selection of his poetic material, partly because of the extraordinary fertility of resource he has shown in the construction of the musical tissue of his work. For Strauss is in reality one of the great musical builders. When belated partisans of the older schools call his music "formless" they simply mean that he builds in forms that transcend their own unprogressive conception of the meaning of the word. To them "form" means nothing more than sonata form; the notion that there can be logic, unity, organic life in a composition put together on any lines but these is inconceivable to them. At bottom, indeed, the question is one not so much of form as of idea. All the music of the giants of the past expresses no more than a fragment of what music can and some day will express. With each new generation it must discover and reveal some new secret of the universe and of man's heart; and as the thing to be uttered varies, the way of uttering it must vary also. There is only one rational definition of good "form" in music - that which expresses most succinctly and most perfectly the state of soul in which the idea originated; and as moods and ideas change, so must forms. The form of the finale of the "Pathetic Symphony," for example, is perfect, because in no other way could that particular sequence of emotions be so poignantly and convincingly expressed. As Mr. Bernard Shaw has recently pointed out, ^* nothing more perfect in the way of "form" could be imagined than the Preludes to "Lohengrin" and "Tristan"; their evolution from the first bar to the last is as inevitable in itself and as beautifully rounded and complete as the slow passing of the hours in the cycle from dawn to dawn. But for some musicians, as has already been pointed out, "form" means sonata form and nothing more; and they would crush all musical ideas into this frame as Procrustes forced all his unhappy captives to fit the same bed. Quite recently a London newspaper solemnly censured a new work in these terms: "The whole work is singularly lacking in contrapuntal interest, and depends solely for such effect as it achieves upon certain emotional impressions of harmony and colour." ^* It matters little to these good souls that the particular thing the composer wanted to say could only be said as he chose to say it, and that a display of counterpoint in the work might have been as ludicrously ineffective as a suit of medieval armour on a modern fencer. The only musical interest, for some worthy people, is contrapuntal interest; and if a composer has ideas that do not call for contrapuntal jugglery - well, so much the worse for him. If a Whistler gets "certain emotional impressions of harmony and colour" from the play of a certain light on a fog-bank he must not try to convey his impressions to others and to make them see the beauty he saw in this vague vibration of colour; he must paint us something tangible and substantial - a "Derby Day," for example, or a provincial Mayor in an aggressively red robe. Any new treatment of a new emotion must be shunned like the plague; the thing to be aimed at is "contrapuntal interest." [Footnote *: In "The Sanity of Art: an Exposure of the Current Nonsense about Artists being Degenerate."] [Footnote *: I cull the quotation from Mr. William Wallace's recent book "The Threshold of Music," p 98.] The wild charge of "formlessness" that is so often flung at Strauss comes, in fact, from a failure to distinguish between form and formalism. As the point is one of the utmost importance to every student of modern music, a little digression upon it will not be out of place. The school that looks askance at Strauss takes for its idol Brahms, who is described by his more enthusiastic admirers as the last of the great German masters, and acclaimed as "a master of flawless form." Now any one who looks at Brahms's symphonies, for example, with eyes unclouded by tradition, can see that his form is often far from flawless. He is less a master of form than "form" is master of him. He is like a man in whom etiquette predominates over manners; his symphonies behave as they have been told rather than as they feel. To say this is not to declare oneself an anti-Brahmsian. One can admire to the full all the profundity, the wisdom, the humanity, the poetry of that great spirit, and yet contest his claim to be regarded as one of the kings of form. With Beethoven the form seems the inevitable outcome of the idea, as all first-rate, vitalized form should; with Brahms the ideas are plainly manufactured to fit the form. The supposed necessity for pacifying this traditional monster is visible on page after page. It cramps Brahms in the making of his themes, which often show the most evident signs of being selected mainly because they were easily "workable." This in itself is a mark of imperfect command of form; we should never smell the lamp in a work of art. Or, to vary the analogy, though a cathedral has to be begun with scaffolding, he is a clumsy builder who leaves pieces of the scaffolding still visible in the completed structure. A picture, as Sir Joshua Reynolds said, should give us the impression of being not only done well but done easily. In Brahms the labour, the calculation are often too apparent. We can overhear him muttering to himself, "Now I must have my theme in augmentation, now in diminution; now I must fit A and B - with what other end in view, indeed, did I make them both variants of the arpeggio of the same chord? ^* now I have reached my double bar, and I must flounder about, more or less helplessly, for a moment or two, till I can get into my swing again" - and so on. The whole movement, of course, is not made up of cold calculations of this kind; but there are enough of them to prove that Brahms was a slave to his form instead of being master of it and to make it impossible to place him in the same category with Beethoven. Such useless academic fumbling as that at the beginning of the repeat in the first movement of the D major symphony, and in a good deal of the first movement of the E minor, quite destroys the vitality of the form for any one who can think for himself instead of believing blindly what the professors tell him. There are too many patches of lead visible here and there in the bronze statue for us to accept it as flawless. [Footnote *: See, for example, the first subject and its supplementary theme in the first movement of the D major symphony.] Strauss can afford to smile, then, at the criticism that calls him "formless" because he chooses to make his own forms to suit his own ideas, instead of, like Brahms, making his ideas to fit some one else's form. And whatever harm he may unconsciously do to foolish young composers who try to imitate his methods, it is safe to say that it cannot surpass the harm that has already been done by the slavish adherence to the so-called classical forms. If the one influence is responsible for much wild and chaotic writing, the other must be blamed for a quite appalling amount of parrot-music that at its best is mere academic primness and at its worst is deadly boredom. The average academy-made composer, indeed, with his tiresome and futile attempts to make living music by the mechanical manipulation of a couple of arid "subjects," reminds us of nothing so much as some poor patient Hottentot rubbing two dry sticks together in the hope of getting a bit of fire. And when one sees how many capable and promising musicians have been stunted in their growth by this system of Chinese compression, ^* one wishes that somebody would write an exhaustive book on "Sonata Form, its Cause and Cure," and present a copy to every student who is in danger of catching the disease. [Footnote *: Busoni has some penetrating remarks on the subject, apropos partly of the finale to Brahms's first symphony, in his "Entwurf einer neuen Aesthetik der Tonkunst" (Trieste, 1907).] Sonata form, in fact, was the special product of a special order of musical ideas - the best possible way of giving to those particular ideas coherence, balance, and unity. But the ideas - especially the musico-poetic ideas - of this generation are not those of the eighteenth or early nineteenth century, and the old methods of building ideas up into large designs are no longer wholly applicable; coherence, balance, and unity must still be sought, but in different ways. It is Strauss's great virtue that he has shown how this can be done. He is as solicitous about "form" as the most hide-bound pedant could be; he himself has said, in reply to a question that was a little indiscreet, "I always have form before my eyes in composing." The defects in his later orchestral works, and they are regrettably many, are not at all of form but of conception - they come from that lack of balance in his disposition that makes it impossible for him to keep the cruder and more freakish side of his nature under; but even when he is spoiling a fine picture by inserting in it details that set our teeth on edge by their inappropriateness or their inanity, he always weaves his threads together, the cotton with the silk, in masterly fashion. In Ein Heldenleben, for example, those of us who would willingly go out of the hall, if we could, while the "Adversaries" are sniggering and snarling and grunting, are bound to admire the skill and the power with which he later on builds the chief "Adversary" theme into the main musical tissue. And as for breadth and scope of design, the orchestral works from Tod und Verklarung onward show a grasp of musical architecture and an audacity of mental span that can be paralleled, in the nineteenth century, in the work only of Beethoven and of Wagner. Beside the power that builds up such an edifice as Zarathustra or Ein Heldenleben, the Brahmsian faculty for going through the conventional forms of scholastic jugglery with two or three fragments of carefully selected material does not seem so wonderful that we should go into rhapsodies over it. As we have seen, Strauss made the transition from abstract to poetic music very cautiously. Aus Italien shows him carefully feeling his way from the one to the other; though he is working upon a programme ^* he still adheres in the main, like Berlioz, to the older symphonic form. The work is in four movements, each bearing a title - (1) "In the Campagna" (andante); (2) "Among the Ruins of Rome," with the sub-title "Fantastic pictures' of vanished splendour; feelings of melancholy and sorrow in the midst of the sunny present" (allegro molto con brio); (3) "By Sorrento's Strand" (andantino); (4) "Scenes of Popular Life in Naples" (allegro molto). All the while there can be seen the contest in the young composer between the traditions of his past and the first stirrings of his future style. The work is formal and free by turns; it is neither pure poetic mood-painting nor pure abstract design, but a compromise or a fluctuation between the two. Strauss had not yet mastered the art of framing his programme in such a way that no clashing shall result between the poetic scheme and the musical structure, the two evolving at the same rate along parallel lines. Macbeth (1886-7) shows a marked advance in this respect; it is really a superior work, from the point of view of form, to Don Juan, which was composed in 1888. In Don Juan Strauss meets for the first time with one of the main difficulties of the symphonic poem - that of combining a mass of disparate material, partly psychological and partly concerned with the narration of external events, in one satisfactory picture. The finest pages of Don Juan are those in which the nature of the programme allows the musician to give free play to his power of pure musical development - as in the first portrait of Don Juan himself, in the duet between him and the Countess in the portrait of Anna, and in the tumultuous final section commencing with the theme in the four horns. The unsatisfactory portions of the work are those - such as the brief suggestion of the country maiden ^* - that are dragged in willy-nilly for a moment without forming any essential part of the tissue as a whole and the carnival scene, where the sudden changing of the kaleidoscope, together with something not quite convincing in the music itself, strikes rather a jarring note. In Don Juan, in fact, magnificent as the work as a whole is, the canvas is a little too crowded and the various parts of the picture are not balanced finely enough. Macbeth avoids these faults by living throughout, as it were, in the one medium. It is all psychology and no action. If Strauss were to write a Macbeth to-day he would probably not be content with the soul alone of the character; he would make him pass through a series of definite adventures, and the score would be half penetrating psychology and half exasperating realism. His taste was purer in 1887; and in many ways Macbeth, though it has never been so popular as the other early works of Strauss, is a model both in its instinctively right choice of material and in its musical facture. There are, it is true, a good many startling effects, but they are all justified by the subject. Strauss makes no attempt whatever to cover the whole ground of Shakespeare's drama; no other character is introduced but Lady Macbeth - and she is really kept in the background the picture - and absolutely nothing "happens," not even the murder of the king. The whole drama is enacted in the soul of Macbeth; apart from the comparatively few bars that depict his wife, the score is entirely concerned with the internal conflict of the three main elements of his character - his ambitious pride, his irresolution, and his love for Lady Macbeth. There is nothing here that is not pure "stuff for music," as Wagner would have said. The musical texture of the work is extraordinarily strong and well-wrought; already the young man of twenty-two makes Liszt seem like an amateur in comparison. For the first time in the history of the symphonic poem, in fact, a musical brain of the best kind, endlessly fertile in ideas and with a masterly technique, is cultivating the form. The score, youthful as it is, already shows the rich polyphonic structure that is characteristic of Strauss, and beside which the homophonic, lyrical style of Liszt seems decidedly thin. [Footnote *: There is not space in the present volume for a discussion of the aesthetic justification of programme music. I have attempted this in the essay in "Musical Studies" to which I have already referred. But comparatively few people nowadays would hold to the old opinion that programme music is the accursed thing. The question used to be regarded as settled by Beethoven's remark about his Pastoral Symphony being "mehr Ausdruck als Malerei." No one troubles about that now, except to note that the symphony itself flatly contradicts the theory. It is, curiously enough, Wagner who is now put up as the bulwark against the insidious invader. His theory that representative music is only fully comprehensible when there is a stage action to elucidate it, and that it is impossible to keep the programme of an orchestral work in one's head while following the music, has received more reverence than it deserves. I have elsewhere shown that Wagner's theory was simply the expression of his own bias towards stage work. If he could not visualize for himself the protagonists of a symphonic poem like Ein Heldenleben, that is no reason why other people, who can visualize them, should give up doing so. And Wagner's own work is an emphatic contradiction of his theory. The "Flying Dutchman" and "Tannhauser" overtures and the "Lohengrin" prelude require us, if we are to understand them fully, to keep in our minds certain sequences of external events without any help from the stage. His orchestral picture of Siegfried's Rhine-Journey again, in the "Gotterdammerung," is programme music pure and simple. The mind has to associate certain characters with certain themes, and imagine certain changes of scenery and action, just as it has to do, for instance, in Tchaikovski's "Romeo and Juliet" overture. But the vast general question cannot be discussed here; and in the text of the present chapter it is assumed that the reader accepts the broad principle of programme music just as he does the symphony, the opera, or the oratorio.] [Footnote *: It is obviously impossible to find space in this little volume for an analysis of each of Strauss's symphonic poems. Many excellent detailed "guides" to them, however, can be obtained.]